By Eric Vandenbroeck and co-workers

Göbekli Tepe revisited part two

As we have seen in part one, whether we go with Hobbes (or Rousseau), we are left with the idea that the most we can do to change our current predicament are a bit of modest political tinkering. Hierarchy and inequality are the inevitable prices to pay for having genuinely come of age yet except what the available evidence shows are that the trajectory of human history has been a good deal more diverse and exciting and less boring than we tend to assume because, in an important sense, it has not been a trajectory

 

James C. Scott – a renowned political scientist who has devoted much of his career to understanding the role of states (and those who succeed in evading them) in human history. The Neolithic, he suggests, began with flood-retreat agriculture, which was easy work and encouraged redistribution; the largest populations were, indeed, concentrated in deltaic environments, but the first states in the Middle East developed upriver, in areas with a solid focus on cereal agriculture – wheat, barley, millet – and relatively limited access to a range of other staples. The key to the importance of grain, Scott notes, is that it was durable, portable, easily divisible, and quantifiable by bulk. Therefore, it was an ideal medium to serve as a basis for taxation. Growing above ground – like certain tubers or legumes – grain crops were also evident and amenable to appropriation. Cereal agriculture did not cause the rise of extractive states, but it was certainly predisposed to their fiscal requirements.1

 

That indigenous doctrines of individual liberty, mutual aid, and political equality, which made such an impression on French Enlightenment thinkers, were neither (as many of them supposed) the way all humans can be expected to behave in the State of Nature. Instead, certain freedoms – to move, disobey, and rearrange social ties – tend to be taken for granted by anyone who has not been trained explicitly into obedience (as anyone reading this book, for instance, is likely to have been). Still, the societies that European settlers encountered only really make sense as the product of a specific political history: a history in which questions of hereditary power, revealed religion, personal freedom, and the independence of women were still very much matters of self-conscious debate,

 

Most people feel a spontaneous affinity with the story’s tragic version, not just because of its scriptural roots. The more rosy, optimistic narrative fails to explain why Western civilization inevitably makes everyone happier, wealthier, and more secure. This is why European powers should have been obliged to spend 500 or so years (as we have seen in the economics of colonialism) aiming guns at people’s heads to force them to adopt it. During the nineteenth-century heyday of European imperialism, everyone seemed more keenly aware of this.

 

European statesmen and intellectuals of that time were just as likely to be obsessed with the dangers of decadence and disintegration. Many were overt racists who held that most humans are not capable of progress and therefore looked forward to their physical extermination. Even those who did not share such views tended to feel that Enlightenment schemes for improving the human condition had been catastrophically naive. As a result, the social sciences were conceived and organized around two core questions: (1) what had gone wrong with the project of Enlightenment, with the unity of scientific and moral progress, and with schemes for the improvement of human society? And: (2) why is it that well-meaning attempts to fix society’s problems so often end up making things even worse?

 

But throughout the argument, all parties have come to agree on one key point: that there was indeed something called ‘the Enlightenment, that it marked a fundamental break in human history, and that the American and French Revolutions were in some sense the result of this rupture. The Enlightenment is seen as introducing a possibility that had not existed before: that of self-conscious projects for reshaping society in accord with some rational ideal.

 

For much of the twentieth century, anthropologists described the societies they studied in ahistorical terms as living in a kind of eternal present. Some of this was an effect of the colonial situation under which much ethnographic research was carried out. The British Empire, for instance, maintained a system of indirect rule in various parts of Africa, India, and the Middle East where local institutions like royal courts, earth shrines, associations of clan elders, men’s houses, and the like were maintained in place, indeed fixed by legislation. Significant political change – forming a political party, say, or leading a prophetic movement – was in turn entirely illegal, and anyone who tried to do such things was likely to be put in prison. This made it easier to describe the people anthropologists studied as having a way of life that was timeless and unchanging. Since historical events are by definition unpredictable, it seemed more scientific to study those phenomena one could predict: the things that kept happening, over and over, in roughly the same way.

 

Social science has mainly been a study of how human beings are not free: the way that our actions and understandings might be determined by forces outside our control. Any account which appears to show human beings collectively shaping their destiny, or even expressing freedom for its own sake, will likely be written off as illusory, awaiting ‘real’ scientific explanation; or if none is forthcoming, as outside the scope of social theory entirely. This is one reason why most ‘extensive histories’ place such a strong focus on technology. Dividing up the human past according to the primary material from which tools and weapons were made (Stone Age, Bronze Age, Iron Age) or else describing it as a series of revolutionary breakthroughs, they then assume that the technologies themselves largely determine the shape that human societies will take for centuries to come or at least until the next abrupt and unexpected breakthrough comes along to change everything again.

 

Technologies play an essential role in shaping society. They open up new social possibilities never before. It’s easy to overstate the importance of new technologies in setting the overall direction of social change. For example, it’s well known that Teotihuacanos or Tlaxcalteca employed stone tools to build and maintain their cities.

 

This, while the inhabitants of Mohenjo-Daro or Knossos, used metal, which seems to have made surprisingly little difference to those cities’ internal organization or even size. Nor does our evidence support the notion that significant innovations always occur in sudden, revolutionary bursts, transforming everything in their wake.

 

While human beings have always been capable of physically attacking one another (and it’s difficult to find examples of societies where no one ever attacks anyone else, under any circumstances), there’s no actual reason to assume that war has always existed. Technically, war refers to organized violence and a kind of contest between two demarcated sides. As Raymond Kelly has adroitly pointed out, it’s based on a logical principle that’s by no means natural or self-evident, which states that significant violence involves two teams. Any member of one team treats all members of the other as equal targets. Kelly calls this the principle of ‘social substitutability.’

 

Another question is whether there is a relationship between external warfare and the internal loss of freedoms that opened the way, first to systems of ranking and then to large-scale systems of domination. How direct was this correlation? One thing we’ve learned is that it’s a mistake to assume these ancient polities were simply archaic versions of our modern states. As we know it today, the state results from a distinct combination of elements – sovereignty, bureaucracy, and a competitive political field.

 

Where two axes of power were developed and formalized into a single system of domination, we can begin to talk of ‘second-order regimes.’ The architects of Egypt’s Old Kingdom, for example, armed the principle of sovereignty with a bureaucracy and managed to extend it across a large territory. By contrast, the rulers of ancient Mesopotamian city-states made no direct claims to sovereignty, which for them resided properly in heaven. When they engaged in wars over land or irrigation systems, it was only as secondary agents of the gods. Instead, they combined charismatic competition with a highly developed administrative order. The Classic Maya was different again, confining administrative activities mainly to monitoring cosmic affairs while basing their earthly power on a potent fusion of sovereignty and inter-dynastic politics. Insofar as these and other polities commonly regarded as ‘early states’ (Shang China, for instance) share any common features, they seem to lie in altogether different areas – which brings us back to the question of warfare and the loss of freedoms within society. All of them deployed spectacular violence at the pinnacle of the system (whether that violence was conceived as a direct extension of royal sovereignty or carried out at the behest of divinities), and all to some degree modeled their centers of power – the court or palace – on the organization of patriarchal households. Is this merely a coincidence? On reflection, the same combination of features can be found in most later kingdoms or empires, such as the Han, Aztec or Roman.

 

Shang China might well be considered the paradigm for what the anthropologist Stanley Tambiah (1973) has described as ‘galactic polities’, also the most common form in later Southeast Asian history, where sovereignty concentrated at the center and then attenuated outwards, focusing in some places, fading in others to the point where, at the edges, certain rulers or nobles might actually claim to be part of empires – even distant descendants of the founders of empires – whose current ruler had never heard of them. We can contrast this sort of outward proliferation of sovereignty with another kind of macro-political pattern, emerging first in the Middle East and then gradually across much of Eurasia, where diametrically opposed notions of what actually constitutes ‘government’ would face off against each other in dynamic tension, creating the great frontier zones that separated bureaucratic regimes (whether in China, India or Rome) from the heroic politics of nomadic peoples which threatened constantly to overwhelm them.

 

James Scott, a renowned political scientist who has devoted much of his career to understanding the role of states in human history, has a compelling description of how this agricultural trap works. The Neolithic, he suggests, began with flood-retreat agriculture, which was easy work and encouraged redistribution; the most significant populations were concentrated in deltaic environments. However, the first states in the Middle East developed upriver, in areas with an especially strong focus on cereal agriculture. The key to the importance of grain, Scott notes, is its durable, portable, easily divisible, and quantifiable by bulk. Therefore, it was an ideal medium to serve as a basis for taxation. Growing above ground – like certain tubers or legumes – grain crops were also obvious and amenable to appropriation. Cereal agriculture did not cause the rise of extractive states, but it was certainly predisposed to their fiscal requirements.1

 

That indigenous doctrines of individual liberty, mutual aid, and political equality, which made such an impression on French Enlightenment thinkers, were neither the way all humans can be expected to behave in the State of Nature. Nor were they (as many now assume) simply the way culture happened to crumble in that particular part of the world. This is not to say there is no truth whatsoever in either of these positions. There are certain freedoms – to move, to disobey, to rearrange social ties – that tend to be taken for granted by anyone who has not been trained explicitly into obedience, is likely to have been. Still, the societies that European settlers encountered only really make sense as the product of a specific political history: a history in which questions of hereditary power, revealed religion, personal freedom, and the independence of women were still very much matters of self-conscious debate.

 

Most people feel a spontaneous affinity with the story’s tragic version, not just because of its scriptural roots. The more rosy, optimistic narrative – whereby the progress of Western civilization inevitably makes everyone happier, wealthier, and more secure – has at least one obvious disadvantage. It fails to explain why that civilization did not simply spread of its own accord; that is, why European powers should have been obliged to spend the last 500 or so years aiming guns at people’s heads to force them to adopt it. (Also, if being in a ‘savage’ state was so inherently miserable, why so many of those same Westerners, given an informed choice, were so eager to defect to it at the earliest opportunity.) During the nineteenth-century heyday of European imperialism, everyone seemed more keenly aware of this.

 

An answer is suggested by the West Indian sociologist Orlando Patterson, who points out that Roman Law conceptions of property (and hence of freedom) essentially trace back to slave law.2 The reason it is possible to imagine the property as a relationship of domination between a person and a thing is that, in Roman Law, the power of the master rendered the slave a thing (res, meaning an object), not a person with social rights or legal obligations to anyone else. Property law, in turn, was mainly about the complicated situations that might arise as a result. It is important to recall, for a moment, who these Roman jurists were that laid down the basis for our current legal order – our theories of justice, the language of contract and torts, the distinction of public and private, and so forth. While they spent their public lives making sober judgments as magistrates, they lived their personal lives in households where they not only had near-total authority over their wives, children, and other dependants but also had all their needs taken care of by dozens, perhaps hundreds of slaves. Slaves trimmed their hair, carried their towels, fed their pets, repaired their sandals, played music at their dinner parties, and instructed their children in history and maths. At the same time, in terms of legal theory, these slaves were classified as captive foreigners who, conquered in battle, had forfeited rights of any kind. As a result, the Roman jurist was free to rape, torture, mutilate or kill any of them at any time and in any way he had a mind to, without the matter being considered anything other than a private affair. (Only under the reign of Tiberius were any restrictions imposed on what a master could do to a slave, and what this meant was simply that permission from a local magistrate had to be obtained before a slave could be ripped apart by wild animals; other forms of execution could still be imposed at the owner’s whim.) On the one hand, freedom and liberty were private affairs; on the other, private life was marked by the absolute power of the patriarch over conquered people who were considered his private property.3 The fact that most Roman slaves were not prisoners of war, in the literal sense, doesn’t make much difference here.

 

We can also look at monarchy, warrior aristocracies, or other forms of stratification taking hold in urban contexts. When this happened, the consequences were dramatic. Still, the mere existence of large human settlements in no way caused these phenomena and certainly didn’t make them inevitable. We must look elsewhere. Hereditary aristocracies were just as likely to exist among demographically small or modest-sized groups, such as the societies of the Anatolian highlands.

 

Social theorists tend to write about the past as if everything that happened could have been predicted. This is somewhat dishonest since we’re all aware that when we try to predict the future, we almost invariably get it wrong – and this is just as true of social theorists as anybody else. Nonetheless, it’s hard to resist the temptation to write and think as if the current state of the world, in the early twenty-first century, is the inevitable outcome of the last 10,000 years of history, while in reality, of course, we have little or no idea what the world will be like even in 2075, let alone 2150.

 

On the one hand, fundamental breakthroughs in the physical sciences, or even artistic expression, no longer seem to occur with anything like the regularity people came to expect in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Yet, at the same time, our scientific means of understanding the past, not just our species’ past but that of our planet, has been advancing with dizzying speed. Scientists in 2020 are not (as readers of mid-twentieth-century science fiction might have hoped) encountering alien civilizations in distant star systems, but they are encountering radically different forms of society under their own feet, some forgotten and newly rediscovered, others more familiar, but now understood in entirely new ways.

 

No doubt, for a while, at least, very little will change. Whole fields of knowledge – not to mention university chairs and departments, scientific journals, prestigious research grants, libraries, databases, school curricula, and the like – have been designed to fit the old structures and the old questions.

 

Max Planck once remarked that new scientific truths don’t replace old ones by convincing established scientists that they were wrong; they do so because proponents of the older theory eventually die, and generations find the new truths and theories familiar evident even.

 

We can see more clearly now what is going on when, for example, a study that is rigorous in every other respect begins from the unexamined assumption that there was some ‘original’ form of human society; that its nature was fundamentally good or evil; that a time before inequality and political awareness existed; that something happened to change all this; that ‘civilization’ and ‘complexity’ always come at the price of human freedoms; that participatory democracy is natural in small groups but cannot possibly scale up to anything like a city or a nation-state. We know, now, that we are in the presence of myths.

 

 

 

1. James C. Scott,  Against the Grain: A Deep History of the Earliest States, 2017,129-30.

 

2. Orlando Patterson, Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982, 10.

 

3. David Graeber, Debt: The First 5,000 Year, 2011, 198–201

 

 

For updates click homepage here

 

 

 

 

 

shopify analytics