The laws of
economics, it's often forgotten, are like the laws of engineering. There's only
one set of laws and they work everywhere. Armed with a knowledge and
understanding of the incompetence on display in military disasters, the more
disconcerting is the growing familiarity which comes from knowing and
understanding incompetence in neo-liberal American economics through a lens
which captures the enduring features and explanations of their performances.
If we assume that
people are not indifferent to the profession in which they spend their lives,
we cannot dispense with the related proposition that people are drawn to
certain careers and professions for reasons that have to do with who they are -
the combination of their physical and psychological make-up, in other words.
Grant this unexceptional proposition and its corollary, and it can also be
safely assumed that people become economists because Economics satisfies what
they most want in the form of lifestyle, discipline, status, rewards, and
overall expression of personality. Indeed, this is the nature of a profession:
its members, by their entry to it and their progress within it, are making the
statement: 'This I believe and will live by.' In some cases, the profession of
belief is public and explicit - as in the obligations medical doctors swear to
discharge in the Hippocratic Oath; in others it is implied but none the less
binding if only because the profession, if it takes professional identity seriously,
requires and ensures compliance, one way or the other, for the great majority
of its members.
In the case of
Economics, the first defining characteristic worthy of mention in this regard
is its excessive belief in the applicability of the methods of physical science
to the understanding of human behavior - what is known as scientism - a
sub-culture which hampers rather than facilitates an understanding of the
global political economy. That is we see it as an ever-increasing web of rules,
restrictions and constraints, presided over by an elite, one of whose motives
is to preserve the status quo. Scientism is quite a magnetic quality in
Economics. Given that there is a need in any society, particularly the society
of states, and most particularly within the dominant states of that society, to
be able to describe and explain the production and distribution of wealth, the
ability to do so within a discourse redolent of physics fuses many motivations.
It is, depending on the moment, a labor of patriotic devotion, as much as
worthy public service; at all times, however, it is also a source of upward mobility
and personal wealth. Equally, but depending on an economist's position within
the relevant hierarchy, it brings forth an opportunity to exert political
influence, most frequently over the lives of generations of people who are
total strangers and presumably towards whom she or he has no hostile feelings.
These in themselves are troubling intimations which only increase when a deeper
appreciation of the attractions of scientism is forthcoming.
Stated succinctly,
scientism provides a defense against certain anxieties, and, by extension,
attracts people with those anxieties and who are disposed to the quality of
defense it affords. Within the discipline, they form a community of sufferers
as much as a community of scholars who are joined, first, by the expectation,
and then the realization of the effective therapeutic gain which scientism
extends to its devotees. What needs to be noted, however, is that this does not
cure or suppress the condition of anxiety so much as it provides a convivial,
secure, and supportive environment in which people with anxieties can not only
operate, but operate through approved outlets for their anxieties, and as their
anxieties might determine, in socially acceptable ways. (Dixon, Military
Incompetence, 1976, p.173.)
In Economics, the
causes of anxiety are readily identifiable inasmuch as they are logical
extensions of the nature of Economics as a discipline, and as a profession,
though the latter is a particular case of a besetting condition with
professions themselves. To approach the former is merely to recall that
Economics was born on the cusp of an intellectual revolution which ensured the
destruction of its seventeenth-century, Newtonian foundations. Choosing to turn
its face from this, it has, throughout its history, retained a Cartesian vision
of a world which is constant, permanent, simple, static, and invulnerable. In
pursuit of this excessively abstract universe it uncritically (mis)appropriated
whole areas of a discipline in debacle (mathematics), and the superseded axioms
of another (physics), made explicit its refusal to confront the former, and
chose data to suit its aspirations, concepts and constructs on an opportunistic
basis, in the course of which, progressively and rapidly, their emptiness
became as obvious as the discipline's comprehensive inadequacy to the phenomena
it sought to understand.
In evolutionary
terms, its aspirations were always unrealizable; it never rose above being a
pastiche of ad hoc stratagems and became, unsurprisingly, practically
irrelevant. In the history of technology and science this is unique, but for
the worst of reasons. Preceding the development of scientific thinking around
600 BCE, the Babylonians and the Egyptians at least had the former: certain
things - in astronomy, geometry, and medicine, for example - 'worked' but the
explanations for their doing so were mythological. It was only under the
pre-Socratic Greeks that explanations entirely from the natural world were
first ventured. Modernity has not consigned this condition to the past. In the
world of the twenty-first century, while it is commonplace for physicists to
use quantum mechanics, leading physicists, Nobel Prize winners among them,
readily concede that they do not understand it, or how it could be what is. Yet
Economics, which defines itself as the science of the production and
distribution of wealth, has neither escaped its theoretical confusion despite
its strenuous efforts to the contrary, nor approached Antiquity's consolation
of providing consistent, reliable, policy-usable outcomes, nor even thought it necessary to adopt physics' humility.
For Economics,
reminders of these failures are constant because records are kept and,
significantly, they are made available in quality and quantity, and from
sources that must be taken seriously. And while it might be the case that
avoidance and denial are possible in the early stages of experience, it must
also be the case that they eventually penetrate and take up residence in the
conscious or self-conscious. Putting the matter bluntly, any evolving awareness
of sustained failure – and remember, this is a failure which springs
significantly from the organized suppression of the unpredictable elements of
human creativity - necessarily induces a chain of anxieties which begin with
the fear of disciplinary professional supersession, which then leads into the
fear of ongoing failure and social disapproval, and, ultimately, the
encompassing fear of disorder resulting from the release of proscribed
instinctual forces which the overthrow of the discipline will entail
(notwithstanding that they exist and have effect anyway). At stake is a
personal professional identity, years of accumulated intellectual capital, and
the return on investment that this promises, always provided that nothing
changes. The question, then, is this: in the absence of large-scale defections
from the discipline, what mechanisms exist within it which allow economists to
cope with rising levels of anxiety born of their own incompetence?
Thus economics
today experiences the triple estrangement of modern consciousness:
cosmologically, it lived no longer at 'home' (in political economy) but in a
rearranged universe; ontologically, it was neither an inhabitant of the natural
sciences, nor indigenous to them - it was an appropriator, or colonizer, of
them - and politically compelled to settle within them for its future
prosperity; and epistemologically, that place was increasingly the perspective
which revealed the world to it. Economics and economists could console
themselves that they resided in Utopia, but they were only etymologically
correct: for all their contrivances that they were creating the perfect
location, they were distant, isolated and, in point of fact, occupied no place.
Economics lived, therefore, 'beyond the Pale,' and it had, and could take
liberties, accordingly. But this was because life beyond the Pale was a
reproach to scientific order - essentially lawless, and colonists, though they
were subjects, were not there afforded the protection of the regnant authority
on the reasonable ground that they paid no taxes to it. Thus it could, and did,
run the risk of lonely exile by refusing to acknowledge, or even to be aware in
the first place, that life essentially within the Pale - its role model to be
precise - is changing profoundly.
By extension, if the
world accorded to what was, essentially, Newtonian mechanics, it was also,
essentially, static; and being static, it was also, with the exercise of
extreme detachment and the expenditure of sufficient scientific effort, subject
to prediction and control. Above all, it was, as near as could be imagined in
human temporality, an entity in perpetuity, existing for all time - where 'for
all time' conveyed an existence coterminous with that of the Earth and its
solar system itself. The modern discipline of Economics was thus naturalized,
and heralded as but another instance of the unity to be found throughout the
universe, in the life of humans as in the ways of the non-human world.
More prosaically and typically, however, the mode of self-disclosed weaknes in Economics has taken two forms:
evasions-through-denials,
such denials covering a spectrum from the methodological to the
quintessentially human; and dementia in the market. The former is well defined
by the extension of Hahn's injunction to avoid the discussion of mathematics in
Economics to the more encompassing realm of methodology, or philosophy, in
Economics. It is variously seen as either a 'waste of time,' or contrary to
common sense; in either case, methodology is discouraged 'explicitly and
boldly.' As well, there is a 'clear reluctance' on the part of mainstream
economic journals to publish articles in the area, and funding agencies to
underwrite relevant research. As Lawson writes of the situation in the UK, 'the
training currently provided and recommended for Economics students tends to be
more or less devoid of any explicit methodological content.' Given the
insubstantial nature of its foundations this might be thought an appropriate
response, a method of avoiding an embarrassing acquaintance with doubt, akin to
those communities and societies which discouraged their lower echelons from
acquiring excessive education for fear that it would encourage challenges to
the established order by redistributing knowledge, and hence, power. Indeed,
the degree to which mainstream economic analysis excises from its professional
deliberations the inescapable context of its being recalls John Ralston Saul's
view that its 'greatest desire is to generalize and institutionalize a syndrome
resembling Alzheimer's disease.' (Saul, The Unconscious Civilization (Ringwood,
Victoria: Penguin, 1997, pp. 4-5).
Moreover, the
self-absolving plea that the assumptions of Economics are only assumptions, and
relatively innocent ones at that, fails, because these same assumptions
disguise the value judgments inherent in the decisions, policies, and
ultimately, the views of the world and the material conditions which flow from
them. In the denial of this nexus is found another instance of the confusion
between the popular addiction to a narrow self-knowledge framed by professional
self-consciousness, and a deeper awareness of the self and its relations
afforded by an understanding of the origins of historical and social habit - a
refusal which, making the modern history of economic theory a tale of the
evasions of reality. In fact the institutional forces at work are also
evidenced by the under-representation of women among those who receive advanced
degrees in Economics, or who are appointed to the faculties of colleges and
universities, especially to senior positions. Through a system which is
insensitive to many women via the fact that, typically, appointment to a tenure
track position (and thus, the tenure review process itself) coincides with the
advent of their principal child-bearing years, thus jeopardizing the former if
the latter is pursued, albeit temporarily. As the research of Colander and Woos
has demonstrated, the option of a fractional appointment for women in this
period, when, and where available, is but poor redress since women are then
penalized by being paid significantly less than their predominantly male
colleagues, and are, on the basis of their decision, often discriminated
against in the tenure decision. Within the discipline of Economics in
universities and colleges in the United States, as of 1994, women occupied only
5 per cent of full professorships and just 10 per cent of all existing faculty
positions - extremely revealing for a discipline with a well-honed (and as we
will see, misplaced) mathematical conceit given that women comprise nearly 50
per cent of all mathematics majors. The gendered nature of economic thought
which follows from the gendered nature of Cartesian thought provides little
support for those who would defend Economics.
It is almost
commonplace to record that 'physics envy' seduced political economy away from
its roots in society towards the end of the nineteenth century. The success of
science, particularly physics, as an exemplar of the ability to control
conditions and predict outcomes, promised a rational understanding of the
economy through the eye of mathematics (with which physics was braided), which,
of course, required a reconfiguration of the study in terms of the methods by
which it was to be understood. In the prevailing view, mathematics was to give
to Economics, and thus to economists, the relevance and, therefore, the
professional status with government, industry, and community, which had
progressively been accorded scientists since the age of Newton. Since, in
Modernity, mathematics was the highest distillation of truth - exact,
unshakeable, and infallible - all that remained for the transformation to be
effected was to establish the necessary axioms, isolate the relevant variables,
and apply the appropriate mathematics which would reveal economic truth with a
clarity without historical precedent.
And Kurt Godel
demonstrated that, while mathematics consisted of several schools, each in
disagreement with the others, none of the logical principles accepted by the
several schools could prove the consistency of mathematics. Even worse for the
status of mathematics was an emergent character of confusion in which
disagreement between the various constructions attended both the question of
what might properly be designated as mathematics, and, within the
constructions, of what might be the proper superstructure. (See also Morris
Kline, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, Oxford University Press, 1980, p.
307-327.)
Thus the valid
charges against Economics made by Tony Lawson - that the discipline is guilty
of uncritically, and in a widespread manner, appropriating mathematics for
systems or conditions for which they are not suited - is a fourth, and only
fourth, order criticism, being degraded, if you will, by the need to understand
the long-standing and significant critiques which attend, in descending order,
science, mathematics in general, and the prevailing, conventional attitude of
economists to mathematics. (Lawson, Economics and Reality, London, 1997, p.
xiii.) Thus, fourth, it is significant because it locates the misappropriation
within a third order critique which, in simple terms, is the foregrounding of a
disciplinary disposition best described as a form of contemptible
anti-intellectualism.
It is however difficult to be original in describing the character, or the
context, of the present. That it is a war that has been underway longer than
the two World Wars of the twentieth century is not in doubt. That its casus
belli was, and remains neo-liberalism is not in doubt: at every turn, on every
available occasion, the belief is repeated among the world's major economic
actors that this doctrine is both an imperative and the only acceptable
principle on which to organize human - which is to say, social, political, and
economic life. Indeed, so dogmatically is it affirmed that the steps to
conducting an offensive in its name are virtually litde
more than reflexes, loosely automatic responses to the stimuli of power and
opportunity. In time, and because of the scope of breadth and depth of the
offensive, the physics of the vortex came into play. States, organizations,
communities and people were irresistibly drawn into its constant round of
frenetic activity, rapid change and destruction. Yet, at no stage did its
strategists require it to undergo the one test of political action, namely,
whether it made things better, or stopped them getting worse for the great
majority of people who would have to bear its consequences.
For updates
click homepage here