The following is a
continuation of our original six part Global Jihad
study whereby we investigate here by analyzing the original writings, that is
what is considered the original version (although even there varying opinions
exist) of Islam.
It should be clear now that the
Qur'an contains passages that justify warfare as aspect of the
foundational narrative of Islam.1 In the words of Ibn Khaldun: In the
Muslim community, the jihad is a religious duty because of the universalism of
the Islamic mission and the obligation [to convert) everybody to Islam either
by persuasion or by force ... [By contrast] the other religions had no such
universal mission and the holy war was [therefore) not a religious duty to them
apart from self-defense.
Similarly, we as we have
been able to proof in The Islam Code, “questions about the justice of fighting
emerged in the context of the early conquests or campaigns to "open"
neighboring territories to Islamic governance. The notion of the Prophet's
letter to the rulers of Byzantium and other empires of late antiquity
instructive in this regard, as are the stories of arguments between Ali and
others regarding the proper mode of response to Mu'awiya, the Kharijites, and
other perpetrators of civil strife. Many of the texts cited as precedents in
the developing discourse associated with Sharica reasoning are in fact reports
of actions taken, or of arguments confirmed or denied, in relation to the
justification and conduct of war in this early period of Muslim expansion and self definition. The brief chapter on jihad in the Muwatta of Malik ibn Anas is instructive.2
It contains a
collection of reports regarding the example set by the Prophet and his
companions. Topics range from the advisability of taking copies of the Qur' an into enemy territory, to the distribution of war
prizes and the proper care of horses. Overall, the point is to suggest the
importance of participation in fighting under those conditions and according to
those norms consistent with the notion of submission to the will of God. Thus
we find Muhammad saying: "The man who fights in the cause of the Lord may
be compared to one who fasts and prays and is not weary of prayer or fasting,
until he returns from the fighting."3
Endurance or
persistence in the task one is given, whether fighting or fasting and
praying-that is the key, for one who gives his or her life to the Lord of the
worlds. Or again, we find Muhammad in conversation, as follows: The Prophet of
God said: "One who spends his wealth in the cause of the Lord will be
called on at the gate of heaven- '0 servant of God, this is bliss!' The man of
prayer will be admitted from the prayer gate, the man of fighting will be
admitted from the fighting gate, and the man of fasting from the gate of
fasting:' Abu Bakr al-Siddiq said: "Prophet of God, for a man who is
called from one gate, there would be no trouble, but would there be one who is
called from all the gates?" The Prophet of God said: "Yes, and I would
hope you would be among them:'4
Such texts provided
the material for the more developed treatises of the Iraqi school. Of these,
Abu Yusuf's "Book on the Land Tax;' which deals with questions arising
from the administration of conquered territories, seems to be the earliest. For
our purposes, al-Shaybani's "Book of the
Foundations;' and within that work, the chapters on al-siyar,
are more interesting and worthy of sustained analysis.5
From the outset it is
clear that al-Shaybani's text approaches the question
of war in connection with broader issues of political ethics. The term siyar, for example, means "movements:' The movements
in question are those between and within two broadly defined
political-territorial associations, namely the "territory of Islam"
and the "territory of war:' The first of these terms indicates the area
within which Islam is the dominant political reality. The second is a generic
term for political-territorial associations not governed by Islam. In the
territory of Islam, the ruler is a Muslim, the system of government is
organized to serve the expansion of Islam, and the people within the territory
are identified according to their participation in various groups, each of
these defined by its relation to Islam. The primary group is Muslims, but there
are also "protected people" (ahl al-dhimma,
mainly Christians and Jews, though other groups could come under this
category), "rebels" (bughat, indicating
groups of Muslims dissenting from the policy of the established leadership),
"apostates" (al-murtadd, meaning those who
were once Muslims but have in some way disassociated themselves from the true
faith), and "brigands" (muharibun,
indicating criminals who prey off ordinary people and live as
"highwaymen"). In the territory of war, the overarching category is harbi (roughly, "war person"). Subcategories, for
example women, children, the elderly, or, in some cases, Muslims residing in
the territory of war, are referred to in discussions of the means of war,
especially with respect to the protection of noncombatants. Al-Shaybani and his colleagues are thus concerned with the
justification and conduct of war in the context of the kind of
political-territorial arrangement outlined in previous chapters. Their
judgments are developed in response to questions like "What is the proper
behavior for Muslim fighters who cross into the territory of war?" or
"What is the appropriate way to respond to Muslim rebels?"
War is a means to a
political end, which is the establishment and governance of a
political-territorial association governed by Islam. We may take this further:
the establishment of an Islamic state is itself a means by which the Muslim
community can carry out its divinely mandated mission of calling humanity to
the relationship with God signified by submission, al-islam.
In this connection, war is a means to a political end (establishing an Islamic
state), which is itself a means to an overarching religious goal (calling
humanity to Islam). This approach suggests that there is nothing particularly
good or bad about war in itself. It is a means to an end, and should be viewed
as such. Resort to war is thus a matter of estimating its probable
effectiveness in attaining certain goals. Notions of just conduct in war are
similarly suggested by the desire to gain particular objectives.
Perhaps the simplest
way to illustrate this way of thinking is to cite a report with which al-Shaybani's text begins. Here the Prophet Muhammad is
depicted as giving directions to Muslim fighting forces-first, to those in
command, and through them, to all members of the army. The text establishes
precedents to which everyone subsequently engaged in the practice of Shari'a reasoning about war will recur. Whenever God's
Messenger sent forth an army or a detachment, he charged its commander
personally to fear God, the Most High, and he enjoined the Muslims who were
with him to do good. He said:
Fight in the name of
God and in the path of God. Fight the mukaffirun
[ingrates, unbelievers]. Do not cheat or commit treachery, and do not mutilate
anyone or kill children. Whenever you meet the mushrikun
[idolaters], invite them to accept Islam. If they do, accept it and let them
alone. You should then invite them to move from their territory to the
territory of the émigrés. If they do so, accept it and leave them alone.
Otherwise, they should be informed that they will be in the same condition as
the Muslim nomads in that they are subject to God's orders as Muslims, but will
receive no share of the spoil of war. If they refuse, then call upon them to
pay tribute. If they do, accept it and leave them alone. If you besiege the
inhabitants of a fortress or a town and they try to get you to let them
surrender on the basis of God's judgment, do not do so, since you do not know
what God's judgment is, but make them surrender to your judgment and then
decide their case according to your own views. But if the besieged inhabitants
of a fortress or a town ask you to give them a pledge in God's name or in the
name of God's Messenger, you should not do so, but give the pledge in your
names or the names of your fathers. For if you should ever break it, it would
be an easier matter if it were in the names of you or your fathers.6
There is much to
learn from this text, which is basic to all Shari'a
reasoning on the topic of war. In it, for example, al-Shaybani
and others found precedent for limiting the right of war to the head of state.
Muhammad, as W. M. Watt's biographical study suggests, was both prophet and
statesman.7 Scholars in the Shari'a tradition saw in
this report an example of his statesmanship, which was to be followed by those
who succeeded him in the office of khalifa. Resort to
war requires an order from a legitimate authority. It also requires a just
cause and righteous intention. So scholars in the Shari'a
tradition understood, as the words attributed to the Prophet echoed in their
minds: "Fight in the name of God and in the path of God. Fight the mukaffirun." The purpose of war is the establishment
and governance of an Islamic state. That state, in turn, finds its purpose in
connection with the Muslim community's mission of calling human beings to
Islam. A just war must be tied to these purposes. And those authorizing it show
that their intention is consistent in this regard by carrying out a specific
protocol, namely, the issuing of an invitation to the enemy.
One might well ask
how the "enemy" is identified. The Prophet's statements seem to
characterize them as mukaffirun, which literally
means "ingrates" and is typically translated "unbelievers."
Staying strictly with the terms of this report, we may say that such people are
identified by their response to the invitation proffered by Muslim fighters.
The mention of mushrikun a few sentences later
provides further specification. Signifying "idolaters" or perhaps
more literally "associationists;' the term often
bears the meaning of "polytheists:' That would constitute a considerable
limitation regarding resort to war, since the category specifically does not
include Jews and Christians. For al-Shaybani and his
colleagues, however, Jews and Christians are clearly among those to whom an
invitation should be issued, unless and until they pay tribute and thus come
under the sway of Islam as protected people. Thus practitioners of Shari'a reasoning would find just cause for war in the fact
that a given people refused the invitation of the Muslims to accept Islam or to
pay tribute and come under the protection of the Islamic state. The procedures
outlined in this report establish a notion of war as a means of pursuing goals
considered legitimate. The nature of the invitation makes it clear that war is
not the first or primary means recommended for pursuing these goals. Fighting
is prescribed only when other means have failed. Although this formula is not a
precise equivalent of the Western just-war criterion of "last resort;' it
is nevertheless an indication that resort to war must follow an attempt to
pursue legitimate goals by nonlethal means. Thus the tradition of Sharta
reasoning already provides an equivalent to the just-war criteria of legitimate
authority, just cause, righteous intention, and (at least) "timely"
resort.8 We might also see in the overarching purpose of establishing and
maintaining an Islamic state something equivalent to the just-war criterion of
"aim of peace:' Proportionality and reasonable hope of success, by which
just-war tradition instructed those deliberating about resort to war to make a
good-faith effort to estimate the overall costs and benefits of fighting in
particular cases, do not show up, at least in this report.
The preoccupation of
the report is of course with those who are not already under the protection of
the Islamic state. As we read al-Shaybani's text, we
come to understand that fighting against residents of the territory of Islam is
also possible, though justified with somewhat different reasons. Governance of
the non-Muslim "protected" peoples, for example, is set in terms of
obligations established by treaties. If the protected peoples violate their
obligations, for example by initiating fighting against the armies of the
Muslim state, then the ruler of the Muslims is justified in disciplining them.9
Again, if rebels rise up against the state, fighting can be justified. 10 In
either case, the overarching purpose of fighting is to restore peace, order, and
justice to the territory of Islam. Protected peoples are to be returned to
their rightful status. The notion that rebels are to be reconciled implies that
war not only is a means of discipline, but is to be conducted in such a way
that any legitimate grievances of the rebels have may be redressed. In the
somewhat different case of apostates, the point is to return those who have
deserted it to the way of Islam or, failing success in the matter, to prevent
injustice by killing them.11 Similarly, in the case of highwaymen the objective
is the security of the territory of Islam and its residents, and the ruler is
justified in undertaking those measures necessary to protect it.12 In an
interesting demonstration of confidence, al-Shaybani
and his colleagues do not address the question of fighting in response to an
enemy invasion.
Right authority, just
cause, and other criteria already mentioned are not the only measures of
justice in war, of course. It is noteworthy that the prophetic dicta also
include matters related to lawfulness in the conduct of war. In particular, the
saying of the Prophet includes prohibitions on cheating, treachery, mutilation,
and the killing of children. This saying, along with other reports of the
Prophet's practice, gave rise to more extensive restrictions on targeting that
should be seen as analogous to the just-war tradition's concern for
"discrimination" or the "immunity of noncombatants" from
direct and intentional attack. Other considerations have to do with fair
dealing in the distribution of booty and with prudence in making agreements. As
mediated by al-Shaybani and his colleagues, the
report does not contain any references to weapons that mayor
may not be used-the typical concern associated in the just-war tradition with
just-war proportionality. Al-Shaybani and his
colleagues built on this and other reports of the practice of Muhammad and his
companions, providing answers to specific questions raised in their own day. In
reading their collected judgments, it is important to remember their role as
advisers at the Abbasid court, which explains their preoccupation with matters
of administration. The following account of an exchange between two of the
early masters of al-Shaybani's school is typical:
Abu Yusuf said: I
asked Abu Hanifa concerning the food and fodder that may be found in the spoil
and whether a warrior in need may take from that spoil any of the food for
himself and fodder for his mount. Abu Hanifa replied: No harm in all that.13
Such questions have
little to do with the concerns of modern military thinking. They are connected
with the questions of the early Hanafi jurists, however, because of their focus
on movements between the territories of Islam and territories of war, and probably
also because of movements in Muslim military organization in the direction of a
professional army.14 The question emerges in connection with the repeated
consensus of the school that booty should be divided only after its return to
the territory of Islam. Such judgments attempt to ensure a just distribution of
the booty, and also to keep the troops focused on their military task. In
dealing with the conduct of Muslim fighters in enemy territory, however, al-Shaybani and others addressed several questions of direct
relevance to our concerns. Thus we read the following: If the army attacks the
territory of war and it is a territory that has received an invitation to
accept Islam, it is commendable if the army renews the invitation, but if it
fails to do so it is not wrong. The army may launch the attack by night or by
day and it is permissible to burn fortifications with fire or to inundate them
with water.15
The first sentence is
reminiscent of the Prophet's directives to fighters. The requirement of an
invitation is critical for establishing just cause and righteous intention. It
also reveals much regarding the overarching religious and political purposes that
war is supposed to serve, and places war within a hierarchy of means to be
deployed in pursuit of those purposes. Here we are to envision a case in which
hostilities have begun. An invitation having been given and refused, the enemy
is tasting the steel of the Muslims. Should the Muslims now renew the
invitation, giving the enemy a second chance to submit, or should fighting be
carried to a conclusion as al-Shaybani seems to
assume, a conclusion that involves decisive victory for the Muslims. The
judgment is in the nature of a recommendation: renewal of the invitation would
be a good thing but is not required.
Commanders in the
field have discretion in this matter. The second sentence, however, moves in a
direction not covered by the Prophet's statements. Here scholars directly
address the question of military means, and they do so in ways that give a
great deal of latitude to the fighters. The army may fight by night or by day
the former likely involving a greater risk of injury or death to the Muslim
fighters, as well as to certain people on the enemy side who fall into the
category of noncombatants. Similarly, the army may utilize tactics that
increase the potential for injury, specifically burning fortifications with
fire or inundating them with water.
Throughout, the text
reveals a strong inclination toward a position one might characterize as
"military realism." Given that requirements associated with just war
are satisfied, and Muslim troops are thus engaged in a legitimate war, al-Shaybani and his colleagues are willing to grant wide
latitude to commanders in the determination of appropriate means. Such latitude
is not total, of course. The Prophet's dicta are clear regarding cheating,
treachery, mutilation, and the direct targeting of children. With respect to
the last, in particular, al-Shaybani and his
colleagues demonstrate respect for early Muslim practice in classifying a
number of enemy persons as, in effect, immune from direct attack. In addition
to children, slaves, women, old people, the lame, the blind, and the helpless
insane are immune from direct attack.16 In addition, the text indicates a
concern regarding the presence, or even the possible presence, of Muslims in
enemy territory-a condition that must have been ubiquitous along the border
between their respective territories, where Muslim and Byzantine forces often
took turns conquering and reconquering particular towns and regions.17
Muslims in the
midst of the enemy are also presumed "innocent," and thus immune from
direct attack, for the lives and property of Muslims had been considered
inviolable from the earliest times. Direct and intentional targeting of any of
these categories of people violates an express directive of the Prophet, or a
legitimate extension of that directive. It also involves dishonor to fighters,
who win their reputation in direct engagement with other fighters. As the
Qur'an has it (2:190): Fight in the path of God Those who are fighting you; But
do not exceed the bounds. God does not approve the transgressors. "Do not
exceed the bounds"; even in the revealed text, the reference is to a
warriors' code. Now al-Shaybani and his colleagues,
guided by the example of the Prophet and his companions, must elaborate such a
code for their day.
As they do so, their
judgments indicate both their adherence to precedent and a disposition toward
military realism. Thus we read the following series of questions and responses:
I asked: Would it be permissible to inundate a city in the territory of war
with water, to burn it with fire, or to attack with hurling machines even
though there may be slaves, women, old men, and children in it? He replied:
Yes, I would approve of doing all of that to them.
I asked: Would the
same be true if those people have among them Muslim prisoners of war or Muslim
merchants? He replied: Yes, even if they had Muslims among them, there would be
no harm to do all of that to them. I asked: Why? He replied: If the Muslims stopped
attacking the inhabitants of the territory of war for any of the reasons that
you have stated, they would be unable to go to war at all, for there is no city
in the territory of war in which there is no one at all of these you have
mentioned.18
One who fights should
employ the means necessary to win-or so it would seem, given the final
statement in this sequence of judgments. That is not all there is to it,
however. In just-war tradition, military policy can be highly realistic even
while adhering faithfully to the guidelines indicated by the just-war criterion
of discrimination or noncombatant immunity. As more than one interpreter
suggests, the idea is that noncombatants are immune from attacks that are
direct and intentional, but they cannot be immune from any harm whatsoever. An
attack that is legitimate, in the sense that it is directly intended as a
strike against the enemy's ability to fight, may result in the deaths of
noncombatants. This outcome may be purely accidental, such as when a child
happens to wander by a military target and is caught in the crossfire. It may
also be foreseeable but unavoidable, as when an enemy's military resources are
deployed in the midst of a civilian population. In this case the deaths of
civilians are the indirect or secondary (in the sense of
"unintended") consequence of the deployment of means necessary to
accomplish a legitimate military purpose. Soldiers whose actions take place
under such conditions are excused from the guilt associated with unjust
killing. Alternatively, the actions undertaken may be described as justified,
though with some regrettable (secondary) effects. This judgment of
acceptability holds so long as the incidence of unintended, collateral damage
is proportionate with the military objective.
Given this line of
thinking, it is not surprising to read: I asked: If the Muslims besieged a city
and its people positioned behind the walls shielded themselves with Muslim
children, would it be permissible for the Muslim fighters to attack them with
arrows and hurling machines? He replied: Yes, but the warriors should aim at
the inhabitants of the territory of war and not the Muslim children. I asked:
Would it be permissible for the Muslims to attack them with swords and lances
if the children were not intentionally aimed at? He replied: Yes. I asked: If
the Muslim warriors attack with hurling machines and arrows, flood cities with
water or burn them with fire, thereby killing Muslim children or men, or
enemy women, old men, blind, crippled, or lunatic persons, would
the warriors be liable for blood money or acts of expiation? He replied: They
would be liable neither for blood money nor for acts of expiation.19
The reasoning is
quite or at least reminiscent of Western just-war tradition during that
same period in history, and its approach to collateral damage. One would be
quite wrong, in the case of just war or of Shari'a
reasoning, to read such a passage as negating respect for the immunity of
noncombatants. The point is that the attacks are not directly and intentionally
aimed at noncombatants. Without this overarching categorization, the military
acts described would be unjust, and those engaging in them would need to make
restitution. As it is, al-Shaybani and his colleagues
are best read as trying to combine military realism with respect for rules that
measure just conduct in the midst of war. In so doing, they mean to establish
norms appropriate to the conduct of a professional army. The judgments advanced
by al-Shaybani became part of a historical deposit
with which subsequent generations had to deal. Not all later practitioners of Shari'a reasoning agreed with al-Shaybani.
Even the title of a text written by the great al- Tabari (d. 923), the
"Book of the Disagreement of the Practitioners of Fiqh on the Jihad and
the Tax [imposed on conquered peoples]" (Kitab al-Ikhtilaf
alFuqaha fi aI-jihad wa 'I-jizya'), indicates the conversational nature of the
discipline. Shari'a reasoning about war constituted a
lively discourse, in which there could be considerable disagreement about the
administrative matters so important to al-Shaybani
and his colleagues. There could even be disagreement over whether soldiers who
participated in an action in which noncombatants were unintentionally killed
should perform acts of expiation, or over the precise categories of people who
belonged to the class of noncombatants.20
In Shari'a reasoning, it is best to think of judgments like
those of al-Shaybani as precedents. As recent debates
in American constitutional law show, the status of precedent in legal reasoning
can be contentious. That seems the case with Shari'a
reasoning as well, with some opting for a stronger, some for a weaker notion of
precedent. It is clear, however, that the notion of Shari'a
reasoning requires a balance between respect for the judgments of one's
predecessors and the need for independent judgment (ijtihad), reflecting the
idea that changing circumstances require fresh wisdom.
By the time of al-Mawardi (d. 1058), the preoccupation of Shari'a
reasoning appears to have shifted from the details of administrative law to the
superstructure of right authority. Consider, for example, the following:
When the Caliph
appoints a governor of a province or city, the latter's jurisdiction may be
either general and unrestricted or special and restricted. General governorship
is of two kinds: regular (by recruitment), in which appointment is made by the
sovereign's free choice; and usurped, in which the appointment is made through
coercion .Governorship by usurpation is coercion in the sense that its holder
acquires by force certain districts over which the Caliph gives him a decree of
appointment, assigning him their management and the maintenance of public order
therein. By seizing power, the governor becomes an independent and exclusive
controller of political matters and administration, while the Caliph, by his
permission, becomes the implementer of the dictates of religion, thus
transforming unlawfulness into legality, and the forbidden into the legitimate.
Although by doing so he does not adhere closely to the conventions of
appointment in respect of conditions and procedures, his action upholds the canon
law and its provisions in ways that are too important to be disregarded. Thus,
decisions that would normally be unacceptable in regular appointment based on
choice are permissible under usurpation and necessity, owing to the difference
between ability and incapacity.21
As al-Mawardi's text makes clear, he presumes that designation of
a ruler is a requirement of Sharica; that the office must be singular (that is,
there cannot be two legitimate rulers, even if they reside in different
cities); and that the person holding leadership must have certain
qualifications, most notably descent from the Quraysh, the clan into which the
Prophet Muhammad was born. It is noteworthy, given other trends in the Muslim
community of his day, that alMawardi does not require
that the ruler be "of the Prophet's household" or "of the family
of the Prophet (or of ‘Ali)"; this was a position held by the various Shici groups. Al-Mawardi further
stipulates that the ruler may be either designated by his predecessor or chosen
by electors. The latter may be any of the number of Muslims who are truthful,
who possess knowledge of the required characteristics of the ruler, and whose
prudence and wisdom make it likely that they will choose the right person. As a
matter of custom, he writes, this role usually falls to the leading citizens of
the capital of the territory of Islam. Thus far, there is nothing controversial
about al-Mawardi's argument. Indeed, it reflects the
standard presentation of Abbasid imperial practice. Similarly, when al-Mawardi comments on "the ministry" (al-wizara), noting that appointment to this office is the
right of the sovereign ruler and that appointment may constitute the minister's
authority as "delegated" or "executive;' he seems to reflect the
standing practice of the Abbasid court. No ruler is able to administer the
day-to-day affairs of a far-flung empire; the Abbasid caliphs tended to assign
many of these tasks to court advisers, the most authoritative of whom held
positions as ministers. "Delegated" authority of a minister, al-Mawardi says, suggests greater independence;
"executive" authority indicates that the ruler himself is setting
policy and restricting ministerial practice to carrying out his orders.
It is in the comments
on "governors" that al-Mawardi's reasoning
becomes creative. Many, perhaps most, commentators read his notion of a
governor "appointed" by coercion as a pure example of realpolitik.22
It was in fact the case from about 935 on that no Abbasid ruler really
exercised power in the style of the High Caliphate. Instead, power was
concentrated in the provinces of the empire, whose governors commanded armies,
collected taxes, and generally carried out the duties of statecraft. Among
these, the more powerful carved out larger territorial units than Abbasid
practice allowed. Powerless to remove such "usurpers;' what was the caliph
to do? By al-Mawardi's lights, the caliph should do
his duty, namely, maintain the unity of the territory of Islam by authorizing
such governors to rule as agents of the Abbasid court. However irregular such a
strategy may seem, he writes, a caliph who acts in this way "upholds the Shari'a and its provisions in ways that are too important
to be disregarded." In effect, the ruler "delegates" authority
to the usurping governor. The latter thereby achieves· legitimation, and the
former hopes to preserve the unity of Islam, as is his charge. Governors must
therefore "uphold the office of the sovereign [the caliph] as a vicar of
prophecy and manager of religious affairs, in order to fulfill the legal
requirement of ensuring its existence and preserving the rights arising
therefrom:'23 Insofar as the usurper lacks formal qualifications, "it is
up to the Caliph to sanction his appointment as a means of winning him over and
putting an end to his disobedience and intransigence:'24 In certain conditions,
the caliph may even appoint a minister to work with the usurper and to exercise
executive power. With respect to war, al-Mawardi's
judgment legitimating governorship by usurpation is a crucial modification in
the notion of right authority. "General" governorship, in particular,
comes with full power to make war.25 There is a sense in which one who seizes
power becomes the caliph's designated minister for political and military
affairs. After al-Mawardi's time (and even, to some
extent, during his lifetime), leaders of the Seljuq Turks played such a role,
holding positions as wazir (minister) or aI-sultan
(the power) in concert with the Abbasid caliphs' role as guardian of Islam.26
If general
governorship comes with the full power to make war, it also imposes duties. Al-Mawardi's comments on this matter are a subject for study
in themselves. As commander, the general governor sees to the formation,
equipping, and morale of a fighting force. He manages fighting against
"the idolaters in enemy territory," as well as against apostates,
rebels, and brigands within the territory of Islam. In the first group, al-Mawardi designates two classes: "those who have
received the call to Islam but rejected it and turned away from it" and
"those whom the call to Islam has not reached:'27 The former are subject
to attack or the threat of attack at any time, depending on the commander's
sense of what is best. The latter, of whom there would be "very few today
on account of the victory the Almighty has accorded His Prophet's mission,
unless there be nations unknown to us beyond the Turks and Greeks we meet in
eastern deserts and remote western areas;' cannot be subjected to a surprise attack.28
The Prophet stipulated that an invitation is required before fighting. For al-Mawardi, such an invitation includes the presentation of
material intended to persuade the unbelievers of the truth of Islam:
"making the Prophet's miracles known to them, and informing them of such
arguments as would make them to respond favorably."29 In a style
indicative of the conversational nature of Shari'a
reasoning, he notes that, should a commander (improperly) initiate fighting
without making an attempt to persuade such an uninformed enemy about the truth
of Islam, "he will owe them blood-money, which, according to the more
correct view in the Shafi'i school, is equal to that due to Muslims, although
it has been suggested that it should be the same as the various amounts of
compensation paid to the heathens according to their different beliefs. Abu
Hanifa has, on the other hand, said: 'There is no compensation for killing
them, and their lives are to be taken freely:"30 One must cite precedents
in Shari'a reasoning; one need not follow each and
all.
"Killing women
and children is not permitted in war or otherwise so long as they do not fight,
owing to the Prophet's injunction against killing them ... God's Prophet ...
has also forbidden the killing of servants and slaves."31 Here al-Mawardi acknowledges the authority of the Prophet's
directives delimiting the range of legitimate targets. He also moves toward the
identification of a general principle that we might see as underlying the
listing of groups that fighters are not supposed to target for direct attack.
The point is not simply that the Prophet identified women, children, and others
as protected groups. Rather, these persons are listed because, as a general
matter, they "do not fight." Indeed, if women or children do take up
arms, they "should be fought and killed;' albeit in ways that maintain
honor.32 In some ways al-Mawardi's account of the
limits placed on just killing is more stringent than that of al-Shaybani and his colleagues. Al-Mawardi
argues that Muslim fighters faced with an enemy that shields itself with
Muslims should stop killing; if the Muslim fighters find it impossible to
continue without killing the Muslim shields, they should stop attacking. Should
the enemy take advantage of this proscription, surrounding the Muslim army while
still protecting itself with Muslim hostages, the Muslim fighters should defend
themselves, trying all the while to avoid killing their co-religionists; if one
of the hostages is killed, the killer must pay blood money and/or make
expiation, depending on whether he knew the religious identity of the one
killed.33
Al-Mawardi shows both the continuity and change characteristic
of Shari'a reasoning about war. Subsequent writers
provide further illustration. Shortly after al-Mawardi's
death in 1058, for example, al-Sulami of Damascus (d. 1106) produced the Kitab aI-Jihad (Book on Armed Struggle). Al-Sulami was not and is
not widely known for his practice of Shari'a
reasoning; he was evidently an instructor in Arabic language and letters at the
Grand Mosque in his home city. Much of his book on jihad has to do with language
intended to evoke action by Muslims, especially those in positions of
authority, in response to incursions into the territory of Islam by aI-faranj, the Franks-that is, the Crusader armies.
Nevertheless, al-Sulami's mode of reasoning and above all his indication of the
formal duty to fight indicates participation in the practice of Shari'a reasoning.34
For our interests, it
is particularly striking that al-Sulami's preoccupation is with defensive or
"imposed" war. Al-Shaybani and other early
Hanafi jurists seem entirely unconcerned about fighting in a context defined by
the success of an external, non-Muslim enemy in occupying Muslim territory. For
al-Shaybani and his colleagues, the focus of war with
non-Muslims had to do with the ways Muslim fighters should conduct themselves
during an incursion into enemy territory. Similarly, al-Mawardi's
preoccupation is with the rights and wrongs of war aimed at expanding the
territory in which Islam is established. His brief mention of the right of a
governor "with limited powers" whose province is located on the
border between the territory of Islam and the territory of war to fight
non-Muslims if they strike first, and without obtaining the caliph's
authorization, is exceptional.35
With al-Sulami, we
have a different idea, and a different context: duty of fasting. Only those
unable by reason of sickness or other incapacity may be excused from its
performance. It seems unlikely that al-Sulami was the first to argue in this
way. However, the precedents he cites do not say precisely that fighting
becomes an "individual duty." Rather, they suggest that those who are
"distant" from the affected area are called to step forward and give
aid. Just how much distance there is between this and al-Sulami's judgment that
the incursions of the Franks make fighting an individual duty is a matter in
need of further exploration. In any case, by the time one gets to the work of
Ibn Taymiyya (d. 1328), reference to fighting as an
individual duty in circumstances of emergency seems to come easily. If, he
writes, the enemy attacks the Muslims, then the duty to fight becomes a
personal or individual duty for both "those against whom the attack was
made and those not directly affected by it."38 Citing the Qur'an and the
example of the Prophet, this scholar, much of whose career was spent in the
prisons of those ruling in Damascus and in Cairo, writes that every Muslim must
provide assistance, even if he is not a professional soldier. In the battle of
the Trench (627), when the Muslims in Medina came under siege, "God
permitted none to abandon the jihad:' Once the siege was broken, and fighting
involved pursuit of the enemy, a different set of judgments prevailed. Ibn Taymiyya writes that the defense of Medina "was a war
to defend the religion, the family honour and the
lives [of community members]; an obligatory fighting ... [Pursuit of the enemy
following the siege] was voluntary fighting to increase the prestige of the
religion and frighten the enemy:'39
Different
circumstances suggest distinctive judgments about the nature of the duty to
fight. Do they suggest distinctive rules? The answer, it seems, is no. Those
who "do not constitute a defensive or offensive power, like the women, the
children, the monks, old people, the blind and the permanently disabled should
not be fought."40 This general rule is supported as the consensus of the
Muslims, the exampleof the Prophet, and Qur' an 2: 190: "fight in the way of God against those
who fight against you, but do not commit aggression. Truly, God does not love
those who commit aggression:' Ibn Taymiyya comments
that "we should only fight those who fight us, if we really want the
Religion of Allah to be victorious:'41
Ibn Taymiyya does suggest that noncombatants may forfeit their
protected status if they "carryon a kind of fighting with words" or
serve as spies, provide transport for munitions, or in other ways participate
more directly in the enemy war effort. Earlier writers had typically stipulated
that women, children, and others moved to combatant status if and when they
took up arms. The principle, in either case, seems to be that those who do not,
or may be presumed not to, participate in the enemy's war effort are not to be
the target of direct attack by Muslim forces.42
This matter brings us
to an emphasis that many commentators view as a special focus of Ibn Taymiyya's judgments about war. He writes that the
"heaviest jihad should be directed against the unbelievers and those who
refuse to abide by certain precepts, like the abstainers from paying zakat
-alms and the Kharijites."43 The case of the tax evaders has drawn
attention from many students of Ibn Taymiyya's work.
Ibn Taymiyya's wording suggests the notion of
fighting against apostates (al-murtadd) and rebels
(al-bughat). Discussion of the rules governing
fighting against these groups was an established practice of Shari'a reasoning. Al-Shaybani
and his colleagues discussed the matter, as we have seen. Apostates were
understood along the lines of the precedent attributed to Abu Bakr, discussed
in The Islam Code P.1. Having received a communication from a particular
group regarding its intention to maintain faith in God and God's Prophet, but
to forgo payment of al-zakat to the common treasury, Abu Bakr declared his
intention to fight in order to compel obedience. Al-zakat, he said, was not
optional for Muslims. Believers must contribute to the common treasury,
administered by a legitimate authority. Those who refused to do so had
"turned" (the literal meaning of al-murtadd)
away from the faith, even if they continued to recite the basic creed and to
perform obligatory prayers. Ibn Taymiyya is
consistent with his predecessors on this matter, even in his discussion of
"the preacher of heresy contrary to the teachings of the Book and the
Sunna:'44 In either case, the wrong has to do with public departure from Islam,
as established and protected by a legitimate authority. Such wrongs are
connected with Qur' an 2:214 and other texts that
stipulate that fitna, or civil strife, is more
blameworthy than the shedding of blood.
Similarly with
rebels. The Kharijites, whom Ibn Taymiyya mentions
explicitly, were an early group understood as "secessionists" (the
literal meaning of the name al-khawarij). According
to traditions consistently cited by practitioners of Shari'a
reasoning, the group seceded from the rightful leadership of 'Ali ibn Abi Talib
(d. 661), the fourth successor to the Prophet. Their secession was motivated by
an objection to 'Ali's approach to conflict with Mu'awiya, governor of Syria
and an opponent of 'Ali. In justifying their actions, the Kharijites cited Qur' anic texts. They understood
themselves as advocates for justice and saw others as moral slackers, in need
of encouragement or, in some cases, of punishment. 'Ali responded with a
mixture of persuasion and force, the goal being to limit the damage done by this
group of "irregular fighters" while at the same time hoping for
reconciliation. Over time the Kharijites became a standard reference for those
who, while well-motivated, committed acts that did more harm than good. In
justifying fighting against such persons, Ibn Taymiyya
again was consistent with Shari'a precedent. It is
the duty of a Muslim ruler to establish and protect the practice of Islam. Such
a ruler does not use military force to make new converts. Rather, the ruler
fights to extend or protect the hegemony of Islamic values in what one might
call "geopolitical space." Even within that space, fighting is not
authorized to force conversion. As Ibn Taymiyya
writes, the protected peoples (ahl al-dhimma), for
example Jews and Christians living under Muslim rule, may be fought only if
they violate the terms of their treaty with the Muslim ruler. Their difference
in religion is not itself a justification for fighting.45
Force is authorized,
however, to protect the establishment of Islam. So apostates and rebels are
seen as a greater threat than those unbelievers who live outside the boundaries
of the Islamic state. A legitimate ruler is authorized, even required, to use
force to limit the ability of such groups to "spread corruption in the
earth" (Qur'an 5:33). Thus far Ibn Taymiyya
seems consistent with his predecessors in the practice of Shari'a
reasoning. He does write as one intent on purifying the practice of Islam; his
treatise on the institution of alhisba, or the public
exhortation of Muslims to fulfill their duties, is indicative of this concern,
as are numerous tracts and formal Shari' a opinions about the danger of
practices that depart from true Islam.46 For Ibn Taymiyya,
any Muslim refusing to perform those duties or to observe those prohibitions
established by Shari'a reasoning is subject to
punishment. If such refusal is a matter of performance only, the miscreant may
be considered an unbeliever, an apostate, or a "half Muslim" -this,
Ibn Taymiyya writes, is a matter on which Shari'a authorities disagree. If refusal is accompanied by
explicit statements to the effect that regulations established by Shari'a reasoning do not hold, the person is simply an
unbeliever. In any case, however, punishment does not rise to the level of
fighting unless departure from duty is accompanied by armed resistance. If such
resistance is present, then punishment with fighting is necessary. Depending on
the circumsta,nce, participation in fighting to
discipline those who have departed from their duties may be a matter for the
standing army, or it may be an individual duty incumbent on each and every
Muslim.
Ibn Taymiyya's zeal for purity in Islamic practice mayor may
not involve an expansion of the typical concerns of Shari'a
reasoning. Where he does seem a bit different from his predecessors is in his
construal of the relations between rulers and subjects. For Ibn Taymiyya, these are reciprocal. Rulers owe it to their
subjects to provide leadership, to govern wisely, to establish institutions
that will ensure that subjects understand their duties and are encouraged to
fulfill them.
Subjects owe
obedience; this is a standard judgment of Shari'a
reasoning. At some times and in some places subjects are compelled to
"omit to obey;' as when a ruler commands something contrary to the Qur' an and the example of the Prophet. This again is
standard. Ibn Taymiyya takes this thinking further,
however; he says that it is a duty of subjects to remind rulers of the demands
of obedience to God's law. Indeed, Ibn Taymiyya
presumes that "commanding right and forbidding wrong" is a task in
which all Muslims have a part. Certainly, not all Muslims are public officials
with rights and duties associated with enforcement of the Shari'a.
But all Muslims do have a share in the task of commanding good and forbidding
evil, and this notion may be understood in ways that expand the rights of
subjects in relation to rulers. For rulers, as well as subjects, may be
negligent in their duties. Rulers, as well as subjects, may depart from Islam
in ways suggestive of apostasy, rebellion, or unbelief. When this situation holds,
who has the duty, and with it the right, of punishing the ruler? The
establishment of legitimate authority, Ibn Taymiyya
holds, is a requirement of the Shari'a. Who will
establish such authority if and when those who hold the reins of power are
themselves corrupt? It is difficult to see Ibn Taymiyya
as a full-blown advocate of just revolution. He wrote in a time when the
unified caliphate presumed by his predecessors no longer existed. With the
invasion of the Mongols, the Abbasid caliphate proved unsustainable, even in
the special role envisioned by al-Mawardi. The Muslim
state was in a time of transition, with competition between various claimants
to power. The Mamluk sultanate in Cairo was preeminent. The Mongols themselves
were in transition; having conquered large portions of the territory of Islam,
they appeared to be quintessential unbelievers. They were, however, in the
process of converting to Islam, and by the time of Ibn Taymiyya
they governed their portion of the territory of Islam by a kind of mixed legal
regime. Judgments associated with the Shari'a were
set alongside those characteristic of the Mongol code of honor. In this
context, Ibn Taymiyya's concerns for pure Islamic
practice seem to suggest the necessity of fighting against the Mongols, and in
certain opinions he appears to say that such fighting is a duty for Muslims.
Such judgments are put forth with care, however; much depends on the trajectory
of the Mongol state with respect to adherence to Shari'a
norms. Thus the transitional nature of authority in Ibn Taymiyya's
time makes it difficult to read his judgments as constitutive of a theory of
just revolution.48
At this point it is
worth pausing for a brief discussion of the differences between Sunni and Shi'i
approaches to matters of politics and war. As we have seen, the Shi'i
insistence that leadership rightly belongs to the designated leader or imam had
implications for the practice of Shari'a
reasoning-specifically, for the idea that the authority of ahadith
needed careful examination, since one could not trust that people who rejected
'Ali and his successors would faithfully transmit the sunna
of the Prophet. Trustworthy or "sound" reports were those transmitted
by, or on the authority of, one or more of the imams. Practically speaking,
this meant that the biographies of those mentioned as transmitters should be
scrutinized, since even the inclusion of the name of a designated imam rested
on the witness of a subsequent reporter. Indeed, in the case of Twelver
Shi'ism, a small group of community leaders, noted for learning and piety, came
to serve as "deputies" of the Hidden Imam, and thus to function as
authorities in his stead, albeit with certain restrictions tied to the fact
that, despite their standing as the imam's representatives, "they"
were not "he:' The role of the 'ulama as, in some sense, deputies of the
Twelfth Imam is the topic of a wide-ranging study by Abdulaziz Sachedina, The
Just Ruler in Shi'ite Islam.49 Sachedina shows that the precise dimensions of
the authority attached to this designation are controversial. Nevertheless, it
is clear that the Shi'i 'ulama perceived themselves as advisers to rulers. In
that capacity, they issued opinions intended to "bind and loose;' that is,
to set limits upon and provide justifications for the exercise of political and
military authority by those wielding power.
In connection with
the Sunni precedents outlined in this P.3 of The Islam Code, the most important
of these opinions have to do with limiting the ruler's authority to initiate
military action to instances in which war is "imposed" by the action,
or threatened action, of an enemy. The great work of al-Muhaqqiq
al-Hilli (d. 1277), for example, begins with a description of the rules of
engagement which is compatible with the judgments offered by al-Shaybani, al-Mawardi, and others
described above. Ai-Hilli then makes clear, however, that he is describing the
justification and conduct of fighting ordered by the designated leader, who, as
the imam of his age, is protected from the commission of serious sin, and thus
knows when war is a proper means of statecraft. In the absence of the
designated leader, his deputies are not authorized to carry out wars in which
the intention is to expand Islamic territory. The deputies' authority is
limited to situations in which the invasion or threat of invasion by a non-Muslim
power provides a context for "defensive" war.
In such a context,
the normal rules governing the conduct of Muslim forces hold. That is, those
fighting in order to defend the territory of Islam are to avoid directly
targeting noncombatants, and to use weapons and tactics that are proportionate
to the task. If the progress of enemy forces raises the specter of an
emergency, then the ruler, and with him the Shi'i 'ulama, call for help from
neighboring Muslim rulers. The Shi'i trajectory, like the Sunni, thus establishes a set of precedents
for the justification and conduct of war. The distinctively Shi'i emphasis on
leadership has important implications for the notion of right authority,
however. As in the case of Ibn Taymiyya's writings,
the Shi'i emphasis on leadership is critical for an understanding of
contemporary militancy, not least in the writings of the late Ayatollah
Khomeini. Indeed, the logic of contemporary Muslim argument makes clear the
role of precedent in Shari'a reasoning about politics
and war. As a living tradition, Islamic judgments about the order of society
and the uses of military force always respond to new situations. Yet both the
shape of argument and the form of reasoning employed by militants and their
critics alike rely upon interpreting and applying historical, textual
precedents set by premodern scholarsor, even better,
by the Qur'anic and Prophetic precedents to which these scholars referred. Shari'a reasoning is a system of argument about the fit
that obtains between precedents and the facts of politicallife.
And so Muslim arguments about war and politics in contemporary settings proceed
just as they did in preceding centuries: by asking "What guidance has God
provided for the conduct of life?" "What is the path that leads to
refreshment" corresponding to the example of the Prophet and the true
nature of human beings.”50
The Islam Code P.1 of 3
1. See Sohail
Hashmi, "Interpreting the Islamic Ethics of War and Peace;' in The Ethics
of War and Peace, ed. T. Nardin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996),
146-168. Also see John Kelsay, "And Why Should You Not Fight? The Imperative
of War in Islam and Christianity;' forthcoming in Linda Hogan, ed., Religions
and the Politics of Peace and Conflict (Eugene, Ore.: Wipf and Stock, 2007).
2. Al-Muwatta of Imam Malik Ibn Anas, trans. Aisha Abdurrahman
Bewley (London: Kegan Paul, 1989), 173-184.
3. Ibid., 173.
4. Ibid., 183.
5. On the history of
the text, see Majid Khadduri's introduction in his translation of The Islamic
Law of Nations: Shaybani's Siyar (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins Press, 1966), 1-74. For the dating of the text and its redactional
history, see also Norman J. Calder, Studies in Early Muslim Jurisprudence
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993); and, more briefly, but suggestively,
Khaled Abou EI Fadl, Rebellion and Violence in Islamic Law (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 200 1), 144-145. The earliest version of al-Shaybani's treatise available to us dates from the time of
al-Sarakhsi (d. 1096), that is, two to three
centuries after the death of al-Shaybani. From al-Sarakhsi's use of the treatise, it is clear that he and his
contemporaries regarded it as a school text, to be used in training scholars in
the Iraqi or Hanafi style of Shari'a reasoning. The
text thus functioned, even at this early date, to communicate consensual
precedents attributed to the earliest figures associated with its
characteristic style. Although we must use the Hamid Enayat, Modern Islamic
Political Thought (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1982); as well as Malcolm
Kerr, Islamic Reform: The Political and Legal Theories of Muhammad 'Abduh and
Rashid Rida (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1966).
6. Khadduri, The
Islamic Law of Nations, 75-77. Interestingly, given its prominence in later
discussions of fighting, this report is not cited in Malik's Muwatta.
7. W. M. Watt,
Muhammad: Prophet and Statesman (London: Oxford University Press, 1961),
summarizes the more detailed presentations in idem, Muhammad at Mecca (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1953) and Muhammad at Medina (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956).
8. According to an
interpreter like Paul Ramsey, "timely resort" is the import of the
last-resort criterion in any case. See Ramsey, Speak Up for Just War or Pacifism
(University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1988), 85. On just-war
tradition generally, see James Turner Johnson, Morality and Contemporary
Warfare (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999). For formal comparisons of
just-war tradition and Islamic thought, see John Kelsay, Islam and War: A Study
in Comparative Ethics (Louisville, Ky.: Westminster/John Knox, 1993); idem,
"Religion, Morality, and the Governance of War: The Case of Classical
Islam;' Journal of Religious Ethics 18, no. 2 (1990), 123-139; idem,
"Bosnia and the Muslim Critique of Modernity;' in Religion and Justice in
the War over Bosnia, ed. G. Scott Davis (New York: Routledge, 1996), 117-142;
Kelsay and James Turner Johnson, eds., Just War and Jihad (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood,
1991); James Turner Johnson and John Kelsay, eds., Cross, Crescent, and Sword
(Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1990); James Turner Johnson, The Holy War Idea in
Western and Islamic Traditions (University Park: Pennsylvania State University
Press, 1997); Reuven Firestone, Jihad:
The Origin of Holy War in Islam (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999); Basaam Tibi, "War and Peace in Islam;' in Nardin, The
Ethics of War and Peace, 128-145; Sohail Hashmi, "Interpreting the Islamic
Ethics of War and Peace:'
9. As in Khadduri,
The Islamic Law of Nations, 218-222.
10. Ibid., 230-246
and 250-253.
11.Ibid., 195-218 and
222-229.
12. Ibid., 247-250.
13. Ibid., 96.
14. See John Kelsay,
'~-Shaybani and the Islamic Law of War;' Journal of
Military Ethics 2, no. 1 (2003), 63-75; also V. J. Parry, "Warfare;' in P.
M. Holt et aI., The Cambridge History of Islam, vol.
2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970),824-850.
15. Khadduri, The
Islamic Law of Nations, 95.
16. Ibid.,
86-87,101-102.
17. Ibid., 55.
18. Ibid., 101-102.
19. Ibid., 102.
20. Portions of al-
Tabari's text are translated by Yasir S. Ibrahim in "A Translation of al-
Tabari's Book of the Disagreement among Muslim Jurists: The Book of Jihad
(Sections 1-49)" (Master's thesis, University of Florida, 1998).
21. Al-Mawardi, Ahkam al-Sultaniyya wa al- Wilayat al-Diniyya,
translated by Wafaa H. Wahba as The Ordinances of Government (Reading, u.K.: Garnet Publishing, 1996),32,36.
22.For example, see
Ann K. S. Lambton, State and Government in Medieval Islam (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1981); also E. I. J. Rosenthal, Political Thought in Medieval
Islam (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958).
23. Wahba, The
Ordinances of Government, 36.
24.Ibid., 37.
25. Ibid., 38-59.
26. On these matters,
see Marshall G. S. Hodgson, The Venture of Islam, 3 vols. (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1974), vol. 2.
27.Wahba, The
Ordinances of Government, 40.
28. Ibid.
29. Ibid.
30. Ibid., 41.
31. Ibid., 45.
32. Ibid.
33. Ibid.
34. For portions of
the Arabic text, as well as a translation and comments, see E. Sivan, "La genese de la Contre-Croisade: Un traite
damasquin du debut du XII siecle;'
Journal Asiatique 254 (1966), 197-224.
35. Wahba, The
Ordinances of Government, 35.
36. In general, see
Jane 1. Smith, "Islam and Christendom;' in The Oxford History of Islam,
ed. John 1. Esposito (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), esp. 337-341.
37. From the Arabic
text given in Sivan, "La genese de la
Contre-Croisade;' 220; my translation.
38. Ibn Taymiyya, Siyasat al-Shar'iyya,
in the translation by Omar A. Farrukh, Ibn Taimiya on
Public and Private Law in Islam (Beirut:
Khayats, 1966), 146. For a short account of Ibn Taymiyya's life and thought, see Henri Laoust's
entry in the Encyclopedia of Islam, 2d ed., 12 vols., ed. E. van Donzel,
Bernard Lewis, and Charles Pellat, vol. 3 (Leiden:
Brill, 1986),951-955. See also Michael Cook, Commanding Right and Forbidding
Wrong in Islamic Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 145-164.
39. Ibid., 147.
40. Ibid., 140.
41. Ibid., 141.
42. Ibid.
43. Ibid., 146.
44. Ibid., 141.
45. Ibid., 142.
46. On al-hisba, see the translation by M. Holland in Public Duties
in Islam (Leicester, U.K.: Islamic Foundation, 1982). On the more general duty
with which this treatise is concerned, see Cook, Commanding Right and
Forbidding Wrong.
47. Taimiya, Ibn Taimiya, 145-148.
48. On these matters,
see Holland, Public Duties; and Cook, Commanding Right and Forbidding Wrong,
esp. 151-157.
49. Abdulaziz
Sachedina, The Just Ruler in Shi'ite Islam (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1988).
50. On these points,
see Etan Kohlberg, "The Development of the Imami-Shi'i
Doctrine of jihad;' Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morganlandischen
Gesellschaft 126 (1976), 64-82; al-Muhaqqiq al-Hilli,
Shara'i aI-Islam fi Masa'il al-Halal wa al-Haram,
translated in 2 vols. by A. Querry as Droit Musulman.
Recueil de lois concernant les Musulmans
schyites (Paris: Imprimerie Nationale, 1871-72). A contemporary authority, the Ayatullah Murtaza Mutahhari (d. 1979), argued that at least in some cases,
fighting in defense of the oppressed citizens of another country may be
classified as imposed war, and seen as an even greater or higher duty than
defense of one's own homeland. See his Jihad: The Holy War of Islam and Its
Legitimacy in the Qur'an, trans. Mohammad S. Tawheedi
(Albany, Calif.: Moslem Student Association [Persian Speaking Group], n.d.);
and, more generally, Bruce Lawrence, "Holy War (Jihad) in Islamic Religion
and Nation-State Ideologies;' in Kelsay and Johnson, Just War and Jihad,
141-160.
For updates click homepage here