During the Thirty
Years’ War, a new type of source of transcendent credibility emerged. In the
middle ages and in the Reformation era, the ruler’s authority was derived directly
from God. However, in the late sixteenth century, political theorists began to
develop theories that envisioned the authority of God passing to the ruler
through an intermediary, the “nation,” “people,” or “commonwealth.” Because the
ruler was perceived as the physical embodiment of the nation, such theories did
not necessarily reduce the ruler’s authority. In fact, when successfully
applied, these theories freed a ruler from the responsibility of protecting the
Church or orthodox belief and allowed him to pursue a foreign policy that
prioritized his own realm over the more amorphous Christendom. Cardinal
Richelieu first successfully applied these theories when he devised French
foreign policy in the Thirty Years’ War. As a result, although his country was
predominantly Catholic, he succeeded in supporting the Protestant war cause
without a loss in the king’s credibility. The success of this policy encouraged
other European rulers to imitate Richelieu’s strategy. Thus, by the end of the
War, the Peace of Westphalia instituted an international system based on this
new theory of “proto-nationalism.”
Proto-nationalism was
a developmental stage bridging the gap between the direct linkage of political
authority familiar to the sixteenth century and the subsequent nationalism of
the modern states system. It differed from later nationalism in that the ruler
was so closely associated with the nation that he was seen as its physical
embodiment. Later theories of nationalism would make popular the idea that the
nobility, a representative institution, or the “people as a whole” embodied of
the nation, rather than the ruler. In proto-nationalism, God granted authority
to the political unit via the intermediary of the nation. When God bestowed
authority on the nation, he thereby made it sacred, a thing that was blessed or
even chosen.448 Thus, the nation became a thing that must be protected because
it was holy. The ruler, as the physical embodiment of the nation, contained in
his person the whole of the authority that God had granted and, thus, subjects
must obey the ruler without question. Proto-nationalism increased the number of
sources of transcendent credibility in the system, which increased the
distinctiveness of boundaries between political units.
The crucial
discussions of political authority in the late sixteenth century involved the
question of whether a subject must obey a heretical ruler. This contradiction
between the spiritual and political life, an inherent part of the theories
developed in the Reformation, generated discussions in which the medieval idea
of the nation emerged as a solution. The addition of the nation to the formula
of political authority proved not only useful for the ordinary citizen, but
also for the ruler who possessed the ability to put it into practice.
The Significance of the Addition of the Nation
The idea that
political authority passes from God to the ruler through the people was not
unheard of in the middle ages. Any discussion about authority in the middle
ages must begin with the Pope. There were two distinct streams of thought
regarding the source of the Pope’s authority. Some argued that the authority
came to the person of the Pope directly from God.449 This, of course, is the
precursor to the divine right of kings theory. Since temporal rulers of the
period struggled to portray themselves on, at a minimum, equal footing to that
of the Pope, they too claimed their authority devolved directly from God. The
second stream of thought emerged in the late Middle Ages from the Conciliar
Movement, in which it was argued that the Pope’s authority came from a general
council of the Church.450 God, it was asserted, granted a measure of authority
on earth to the Church, meaning the community rather than any single person.
This council, then, passed some of its inherited authority on to the Pope. The
latter stream suggested that authority progressed from God to the ruler through
the community, while the former stream argued that the link was direct. Each
perspective was further developed in early modern Europe.
That the ruler’s
authority came directly from God was an idea that flowed unabated into the
Early Modern period. The supporting scriptural credentials had been well
developed. Chapter 13 of Paul’s Epistle to the Romans clearly stated: “Let
everyone obey the authorities that are over him, for there is no authority
except from God, and all authority that exists is established by God.”
Theologically there were no exceptions – it included Christian kings, tyrants,
and heathen rulers. In addition, hould a coup occur,
then theoretically the new ruler would be as “established by God” as the
old. The political rebel had no place in the theology of Paul: “The man who
opposes authority rebels against the ordinance of God.” Treason became
punishable here on earth and in the afterlife. Political theories condoning
resistance were likewise considered heresy. Although these verses protected the
ruler’s position, they did not enhance his credibility. Later in the chapter,
as Paul described the ruler as “God’s servant,” the implication was not that
all rulers actively serve God, but that God uses all rulers, Christian or
heathen, as his tools to reward and punish humanity.
Romans 13 could be
and often was interpreted as a manifesto in support of the political status
quo. Christian rulers enjoyed a special position in the unfolding of God’s
plans on earth and rulers anxiously encouraged the clergy to continuously
remind the people on this score. The middle ages did not see the development of
a full-blown theory of the “Divine Right of Kings.”451 The lack of such a
theory had two primary causes. First, the power and prestige of the Papacy
precluded such an idea. From the Pope’s perspective, only he inherited the
“keys of the kingdom,” placing him at the forefront of Christendom. The papal
bull Unam Sanctam (1302) officially stated this
theory.452
Only God could hold
temporal rulers accountable, but he did so through his earthly mouthpiece – the
Pope. Thus, the Pope possessed the authority to excommunicate rulers who
violated the will of God and, if necessary, interdict entire realms. The Pope
could generate compliance from a ruler’s population to a degree he was no
longer able to achieve in the early modern period.453
A second reason
Divine Right did not emerge in the middle ages is that rulers simply had to
contend with a powerful set of nobles who had incentives to perpetuate an
interpretation of the Christian source of transcendent credibility in which
they possessed credibility rivaling that of the king.454 The feudal system
ensured that, while a monarch may be first among equals, he was still merely
one of the nobility.
Everything in the
ruler-noble relationship, from the economy to the military, guaranteed that a
ruler must consult with and listen to the lords of his realms. The nobility
relied on the same theological arguments that the ruler did.455 Thanks to
Romans 13, even at these lower political levels rebelliousness entailed sin.
These two medieval obstacles to Divine Right theory declined in the early
modern period: the Pope’s prestige had faded decidedly and, in many areas, the
nobles no longer held the same ability to check the authority of the king.456
Under a Divine Right
formulation the ruler’s behavior was still seen as limited. Theologically, this
was because God was self-limited. An important debate regarding the
relationship between God and natural law raged during the late sixteenth and
early seventeenth century.457 On one side were those who said God was
omnipotent and therefore unlimited in power. In the mid-seventeenth century,
several royal absolutists (such as Hobbes and Filmer) would associate their
political position with this absolutist theological position.458 However, many
theologians and mathematicians challenged this view, arguing that two plus two
still equaled four for God. He created natural law and then he bound himself to
this law. If God’s power was limited, albeit under by his own will, then the
ruler’s power must be limited as well.459 Divine Right theories at the turn of
the seventeenth century did not find this latter interpretation antithetical
primarily because such a construction was not considered a real limitation on
the power of God or the monarch. After all, the king legislated and interpreted
the laws, so he could not realistically break them. Some even argued that the
ruler would not break the law if he could since that would be contrary to his
nearly divine nature.
The medieval concept
of the “common good” was considered another limitation on the power of the
ruler. Thomas Aquinas agreed with Aristotle that government is necessary – not
a necessary evil as Augustine portrayed it, but a necessary good. To live in a group
is “a necessity of man’s nature,” and this requires a government.460 Since
there is One God governing creation, it stands to reason that rule by one
person is the best form of government. As God’s representative, his actions
“should be directed toward securing the welfare of that which he undertakes to
rule,” namely his people.461 Most of this logic would remain unquestioned for
hundreds of years. Even those in the conciliar movement who stressed the
authority of the group recognized that one of the first functions of the
council must be to select a single ruler. The goal of “welfare” of the people
or even “common good” also was not disputed (except perhaps by Machiavelli).
The question was not whether a ruler had limits on his behavior. The questions
were who decided when those limits had been violated and who imposed a
punishment for out-of-bounds behavior.462
The ambiguity of the
terms “welfare” and “common good” narrowed the core of the discussion on
political authority in the Early Modern period to a
overwhelming concern: who defined “welfare?” Only a very few claimed the
judgment belonged to the people as a whole. More argued that it belonged to a
representative body of the people, such as a parliament. They cited the
precedent of the Magna Carta of thirteenth century England, where the nobles
successfully grabbed their right to define welfare. In Early Modern Europe,
however, the growing bureaucratization of royal courts permitted kings to
reassert the claim that they alone defined welfare, agents accountable only to
God. In many cases, rulers now possessed sufficient power and independence to
reasonably back that claim up.
Hamstrung by the
commandments in Romans 13, early Protestant reformers in the first half of the
sixteenth century offered no alternative. Martin Luther and John Calvin each
supported a literal reading of this passage, even in places where Protestant
congregations found themselves persecuted. In England, Henry VIII and Thomas
Cromwell used Luther’s and William Tyndale’s doctrines of obedience to convince
the Parliament that the ecclesial structure erected by the king should be
acquiesced to without question.463 Thus, any opposition to the growing Divine
Right ideologies between 1500 and 1570 either came from the Radical Reformers
or from Catholic nobles who were relatively secure from the growing Protestant
movement.
James I of England,
who argued that when a king is crowned, he “becomes a natural Father to all his
Lieges.” His “fatherly duty is bound to care for the nourishing, education, and
virtuous government of his children.”464 In short, it was he who provided for
and decided the welfare of his subjects. It was not for the subjects to
question the King any more than nature allowed children to question their
father. The King was “to be judged only by God, whom to only he must give count
of his judgment.”465 James extended this idea in a speech he gave in 1609.
Kings were not merely fathers, but gods — “even by God himself they are called
Gods.”466 They were justly called this because “they exercise a manner or
resemblance of Divine power upon earth.”467 He would later, in 1616, explain to
the Star Chamber: “It is Atheism and blasphemy to dispute what God can do: good
Christians content themselves with his will revealed in his word. So, it is
presumption and high contempt to dispute what a King can do, or say that a King
cannot do this, or that.”468
It is uncertain the
extent to which Early Modern theories interposed the “people” between God and
the ruler owed a debt directly to the conciliar movement. The conciliar
movement was not anti-Church or even anti-Pope. It merely argued that the
spiritual authority God gave to men depended on the consensus of the leaders of
the Church as representatives of the larger community. The Pope could still be
considered “infallible,” since this was both a part of the authority granted
him and a means of holding him in check.469 On the other hand, Protestant
theorists of the Early Modern period who used similar reasoning had different
goals in mind. First of all, when they argued that God granted authority to His
“Church,” they did not mean the Roman Catholic Church, but what they argued was
the True Church or the reformed church. Reformers did not see themselves as
“breaking away” from the Catholic Church, but reconstructing the Church along
the model God had originally intended.
To these reformers,
it was the Roman Catholic Church that broke away from God’s Church. Secondly,
this theory mirrored the political situation in many of the towns of northern
Germany and the Low Countries where Protestantism had most thoroughly taken root.
Authority in these cities came from town councils, invested with power from the
citizens. These councils could likewise create mayors. God was not perceived as
directly appointing the officers of temporal authority in these urban areas. A
theory of mediated authority killed two birds with one stone: it justified the
actions of the Protestant Reformation and the political institutions already in
existence in much of the urban North. Thus, it is possible to explain the
existence of the theory in the early modern period without drawing direct links
to the conciliar movement.
Catholic rulers’
continued persecutions of Protestant congregations sparked some of these
reformers to generate theories of resistance. A theory of resistance was
impossible for both Catholics and Protestants so long as it was believed that
God directly granted a ruler’s political authority.470 The most logical answer
politically and theologically was to develop a theory of mediated authority in
which the ruler’s authority passed first through the community. The English
restoration of Catholicism under Queen Mary (1553-58) became the first
large-scale laboratory in which Protestants developed these theories of
mediated authority and resistance.471 During this same decade, Scotland saw
reformer John Knox publish numerous tracts against the Catholic regent Mary of
Guise and Mary Queen of Scots that argued the people have the right and
responsibility to determine whether their ruler was obeying God and resist and
kill ungodly magistrates.472 More controversially, the Scottish reformer George
Buchanan wrote that Romans 13 was intended only for the historical context in
which it was written: Christians in the Apostle Paul’s day were not powerful
enough to overthrow their Roman tyrants. The situation was very different in
the sixteenth century, however. People gave authority to kings in exchange for
protection.
When a ruler no
longer fulfilled his side of the bargain, the people could depose or kill
him.473 The installment of Protestant rulers in England and Scotland forced the
next generation of Protestants to back away from theories of resistance that
justified regicide – even as Catholic theorists began to develop theories of
resistance of their own. However, the notion that authority was derived from
the community endured among many Protestants, especially those associated with
Parliament.474
It was during the
French Wars of Religion (1562-98) that the theory of resistance came into its
own. Before 1572, most Huguenots remained staunch supporters of the king, even
as they rejected Catholicism.475 If there existed a unified “Huguenot strategy”
it was to replace the king’s Catholic advisors with Protestants. However, the
St. Bartholomew’s Day Massacre of 1572 and its aftermath convinced many
Huguenots that the king stood firmly on the side of evil (i.e. Catholicism) and
must be resisted.476 Like their predecessors in England and Scotland, the
Calvinists in southern France developed a theory of resistance that placed the
“people” between God’s grant of authority and the ruler’s exercise thereof.
Since God transmitted authority to the king via the people, the king was not
free to act in any manner he desired and claim God as his sole judge. A right
to resistance demanded a theory of political authority that disconnected God
and the ruler. Perhaps the most influential tract published by the Huguenots during
this period is Vindiciae contra Tyrannos
(A Defense of Liberty against Tyrants), written in 1579 by an unknown
Huguenot.477 A ruler’s ultimate authority stemmed from God.
However, “the people
establish kings, puts the scepter into their hands, and who with their
suffrages, approve the election.”478 This was not a usurpation of God’s right.
On the contrary, “God would have it done in this manner, to the end that the
kings should acknowledge, that after God they hold their power and sovereignty
from the people.” This is “to the end that Kings may always remember that it is
from God, but by the people, and for the people’s sake that they do reign, and
that in their glory they say not (as is their custom) they hold their kingdom
only of God and their sword, but withal add that it was the people who first
girt them with that sword.”479
Thus, when the king
acted contrary to the will of God (in this case meaning that he persecuted and
rejected the Huguenot doctrines), the people stood in a position within the
hierarchy of authority to judge his actions and, if necessary, resist. It must be
pointed out that the Vindiciae did not advocate mob
rule. The “people” could resist only if their recognized leaders, in this case
the Huguenot nobles and clergy, had judged the king as guilty of opposing God
and, as a result of this determination, called for resistance.480 If these
conditions were met such resistance would not be heresy, but, on the contrary,
the responsibility of the servants of God.
Thus, in the Huguenot
theory of resistance, the “people,” not just the monarch and clergy, were
considered “servants of God,” and had been given a charge that required
collective action. Having been given one responsibility, it seemed perfectly
logical that God should give the people other tasks in the fulfillment of His
divine purpose. Here, then, was not merely a loose collection of individuals,
but a divinely recognized corporate unit. God interacted with the collective
people just as he would an individual. It was not merely the sum of its parts,
but something much greater, it was a “nation.”
The idea that
authority flowed from God to ruler through the consent of the people did exist
among a few medieval authors. The popularity of Aristotle and Cicero in the
late middle ages meant that there was awareness that the Greeks and Roman
Republicans highly valued this political idea.481 However, until the
Renaissance these classical political ideas belonged to a time before Christ
and, thus, required adaptation. John of Paris, for example, attempted to
combine classical political ideas with those of medieval Christianity. For
John, all legitimate authority came from God, but God granted each community
the choice of which individual would exercise that authority. Thus, royal power
was “from God and from the people who elect a king by choosing either a person
or a royal house.”482 Note that John’s theory said nothing about whether this
consent was repeatedly sought or tacitly implied. Once consent had been given,
albeit hundreds of years ago, the people’s consultation might be complete. This
was very different from the early modern theories of resistance, though it
adopted the same methodology of inserting the community or nation between God
and ruler.
It is crucial to
emphasize at this point that the “Nation,” or to be more specific, the
“French,” had a very different meaning than it does today. The king was to aim
for the common good of the people. But, who determined what was or was not for
the common good of the people? It was with respect to this crucial distinction
that absolutist and constitutionalist theories of government separated.483 The
constitutionalist argued that the people decided for themselves or, at the very
least, the ruler consulted the people through formal institutions when defining
the common good. For the absolutist, the king (or his appointed ministers)
defined the common good, or the “national interest.” As a result, the
absolutist argued that regardless of how the ruler received his authority, the
people lacked an adequate understanding of what was and was not in their
interest; thus, they were in no position to judge.
Thus, if the modern
phrase “government by the people and for the people” were presented to the
absolutists Cardinal Richelieu and King Louis XIV, they would have had no
objections to it. The king was the embodiment of the nation and acted in its
best interests. They would have rejected the notion that the phrase implied the
right and duty of the “people” to hold the monarch accountable. The nation was
not merely a sum of its individuals. “France” was something greater than a sum
of all Frenchmen. The king’s sovereignty and authority was derived from God via
this entity. The people could not control this “more-than-the-sum-of-its-parts”
entity – the nation – because the inferior could not have authority over the
superior. The king, on the contrary, was the physical embodiment of the nation.
He was France. Louis XIV supposedly boasted “I am the state.” One of Louis’
bishops’ put it this way: “The will of all the people is included in his.”484
The absolutist monarch was “government by the people for the people.”
This theory of political
authority also differed from social contract theories that developed in the
seventeenth century. Social contract theory argued that political institutions
were neither God-given nor natural. For a variety of reasons, men voluntarily
chose to leave the State of Nature, pool their consent, and form a government.
In order for this to occur, each person required some assurance that he was not
being left defenseless against every other person. Therefore, social contract
theory imagined that each person signed a hypothetical (though binding)
contract with every other person, thereby creating a collective government and
protecting some individual privileges. Although often implied, this was
followed with a second contract between the ruler and the ruled with the same
end in mind.485
A contractual
relationship was absurd without an enforcement mechanism capable of punishing
violations. Three basic mechanisms were argued to exist. First, God was the
neutral third-party adjudicator. Ultimately, all Christian confessions believed
the ruler who violated his part of the contract had to face the judgment of
God, if not in life then in death. This mechanism had the advantage of
preserving many of the conclusions of the absolutist theories. Other princes
constituted a second enforcement mechanism. Natural Law theorists had long
argued that it was just to use force to compel a tyrant to cease mistreating
his subjects. In the sixteenth century, the Spanish Jesuit Francisco de Vitoria
argued in his treatise On the Indians that Spain was justified in waging war
against rulers in the Americas that forbade the preaching of Christianity or
oppressed native converts.486 European rulers eventually rejected this
mechanism, however. They responded to an increase in the number of sources of
transcendent credibility in the mid-seventeenth century by making internal
matters of state off-limits to other rulers. Finally, a third mechanism to
enforce the contract between ruler and ruled asserted that the injured party
possessed the right to nullify the contract. When the ruler failed to fulfill
his part of the contract, the contract was void.This,
of course, renewed the debate over who spoke for the “ruled” and possessed the
authority to declare the contract void. The answer in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries was resoundingly the nobility and the wealthy, in other
words, the “best” of the ruled. The seventeenth century conditions that
prompted the development of social contract theories favored approaches that
stressed this third enforcement mechanism.487
In social contract
theory the authority of the government stemmed from this contract and from the
parties that were signatories thereof. While social contract theories gained in
popularity and use through the rest of the century and into the next, many in
the population believed any contract was still ultimately dependent on God.488
A bridge was required linking the credibility of God with the credibility of
the nation.The theories pursued by Machiavelli, Jean
Bodin, and Cardinal Richelieu allowed the nation to appropriate and perpetuate
the credibility that had been held by God. Though it may have been an
unintentional outcome, once the nation possessed enough credibility to stand on
its own, at least in part, God was able to drift into the early retirement of
Deism without a concomitant threat to political order and stability.Many
narratives of political authority skip over this intermediate step because
their thematic focus is the progression from absolutism to constitutionalism.
This process, whereby the torch of transcendent credibility was passed from God
to the nation, is crucial to understanding current ideas about the legitimation
of authority.
Thus, authority
derivation became mediated, progressing from God to nation to monarch, rather
than directly from God to monarch, as in a Divine Right theory. However, even
though an intermediate step was added in the derivation of authority, the
nation and the monarch remained nearly synonymous. This made it very different
from modern nationalism. Because this early use of the nation foreshadowed
later developments, we may refer to it as “proto-nationalism.” This constituted
a transition stage between the period in which God was the source of
transcendent credibility and a later era when the nation alone functioned as
the source. In proto-nationalism, the nation of France was an entity recognized
and sanctioned by God. Louis XIII (or more precisely, his minister Richelieu)
claimed authority to act in the interests of France and as the embodiment of
France.
Proto-nationalism’s
addition of this intermediate step gave a monarch many new options. First,
religious division within the realm no longer hobbled the monarch to the same
degree it once did. It was not coincidental that it is France that pioneered
this new theory of political authority. The Wars of Religion in the last half
of the sixteenth century and the tenuous peace maintained under the Edict of
Nantes increased the salience of the issue of religion. Under the new
conception, every Frenchman owed allegiance to the king, whether or not they
were Protestant or Catholic. The continued struggles later in the century
revealed that this transformation was not an easy process.489 Under the cover
of proto-nationalism, Richelieu and Louis XIV re-imposed Catholicism on France
through overt and covert means. After nearly everyone in France was Catholic
again following the Revocation of the Edict of Nantes, it became easier for the
state bureaucracy to transfer the onus from religion to nationalism.
Second, the addition
of the intermediate step increased the options in foreign policy. The Catholic
Habsburgs had been a threat to the realm of the French monarchs for a century
and a half, but they shared a source of transcendent credibility. On the other
hand, Protestant areas in the Low Countries threatened France’s source of
transcendent credibility, but were much less of a threat physically. Thus,
France was beset with contradictions in foreign policy. Adding the intermediate
step of nation allowed France to ally with “heretic” rulers and war against
more powerful coreligionists.
In short, once
France’s source of transcendent credibility shifted from Catholic Christianity
to nationality (or “France”), the largest physical threats simultaneously
became the largest threats ideologically, greatly reducing the potential for
foreign policy contradictions. The intermediate step was useful for a third
reason: it allowed the monarch to openly act in the interests of France rather
than Christendom. In the middle ages, when the Pope summoned a Crusade, many
kings and lords often dropped everything and, at great expense, marched toward
the Holy Land. Similarly, the Catholic Church urged the formation of Catholic
Leagues and other internal measures to eradicate the Protestant heresy in the
sixteenth century. Inasmuch as the credibility of the ruler depended on the
support of the Catholic Church, the interests of a realm occasionally coincided
with the interests of a greater Christendom, but not always. The insertion of
the “nation” in the process of authority derivation allowed kings to openly set
aside the idea of Christendom in favor of the national interest, or in the
language of the day, raison d’etat. Kings could, in effect, pursue the
self-interest of their kingdom unabashedly, as a duty God had placed on them.
Rulers who possessed
the necessary power to pursue what they saw as the “national interest” thrived
under this new conception. Any threat against the nation could be spun as a
threat against an entity God had created and infused with authority.In
addition, it was a small step from God-created to God-blessed to God-chosen.
The language of the Old Testament in which God chooses the nation of Israel
became part of the mythos of many of the early nationalist movements of the
period. As a result of these changes, smaller and weaker realms suddenly found
themselves alone, without the implied support of co-religionists. On the other
hand, this vulnerability could be compensated with alliances that would have
been impossible (at least openly) before.
Nationalism, then, is
analogous to the dogmas and traditions of a religion. The efficacy of a
nation’s credibility depends on the narratives that are told about it to
succeeding generations. The heroes of the nation gradually replaced the
function of the saints. Speeches, stories, and even law, fulfill the role of
proverbs and dmonitions of Scripture. Government,
bureaucracy, and the courts supplant the Church and clergy as the primarily
interpreters of doctrines. It is likely that both intentional and unintentional
efforts were necessary to successfully sanctify the nation. Not only did
nationalism resemble religion in its doctrinal and institutional forms, it
could also mimic its function within the society: providing a source of
transcendent credibility governments could use to more effectively generate
compliance from the population.
This transitional
“proto-national” phase differed from more modern versions of nationalism in
that it depended on the added credibility that Catholicism provided. It was
neither the Catholic God nor “France” alone that emerged as the source of
transcendent credibility, but a melding of the two. The people of the nation
were portrayed as a “chosen people.” Thus, religion was not jettisoned as a
source, but used in a new manner. The religion piece of the equation became
less and less important as time progressed, though it has not completely
disappeared as the 2004 United States’Presidential
election demonstrated. God (and gods) became seen as acting in history through
nations, rather than merely transcending them.490
Proto-nationalism
This shift to
proto-nationalism developed in the writings of three important Early Modern
theorists. Perhaps it is unfair to group Machiavelli, Bodin, and Richelieu
together. Each lived in a different time from the others and promoted protonationalist ideas for very different reasons. While
Richelieu probably had read Bodin and both Frenchmen were more than likely
familiar with Machiavelli’s theories, there is no evidence of an piphanous moment where one writer radically transformed the
way of the thinking of another. And still, there was a common strand of thought
that ran through each that was different from other theories of political
authority in the period: political authority passed from God to ruler through a
new, very subtle, intermediate step of a nation. The nation was a political
community created by, in relationship with, and in some cases chosen by God.
Yet, in these early theories the nation and the ruler were described as nearly
synonymous: authority passed almost instantaneously from the nation to the
ruler at the moment God passed authority to the nation. This made these
theories different from modern theories of political authority.
Machiavelli reversed
the medieval ends-means relationship between politics and religion. Theorists
of the Middle Ages, driven on by the looming presence of Augustine’s City of
God, understood that the role of government was to create an atmosphere that was
conducive to salvation of the soul.491 Whether the sword of the state was
wiping out heresy or maintaining peace in the realm, the government existed to
allow God to work among the people. Fifteenth and sixteenth century Humanists
largely preserved this relationship. Erasmus, for example, argued that the goal
of the Christian prince must always be to live virtuously. All the good things
of government would materialize if the prince were virtuous. 492 Machiavelli
criticized this conclusion, saying that, in fact, the “virtuous” prince was the
biggest sucker in Christendom. Other people would jump at opportunities to
exploit the virtuous, and certainly naïve, prince to the detriment of the
people he ruled, thereby defeating the purpose of government.
Thus, the goal of the
prince must be survival and glory, because only once he had achieved these
could the prince protect his people. Although Machiavelli believed that the
virtue of Erasmus’ prince would rub off on the people, others would take
advantage of them and wipe them out. On the other hand, the glory of
Machiavelli’s prince would also transfer to the people and they would then be
able to protect themselves and survive. Machiavelli’s study of the Ancient
Romans and contemporary rulers led him to this conclusion. Government did not
exist to protect religion or religious belief-these things existed to preserve
government.493
He illustrated this
principle in his Discourses in which he described how Numa, an early king of
the Romans, “turned to religion as the instrument necessary above all others
for the maintenance of a civilized state”494 Numa fabricated conversations with
a nymph to convince the people of the validity of the religious institutions
and ideas he was establishing. Machiavelli concluded that all legislators and
wise men ultimately “have recourse to God.”495 In other words, religion served
as a means to the end of politics.
In the final chapter
of The Prince, Machiavelli proclaimed that an Italian leader should follow his
prescriptions, unite Italy, and evict the foreign armies from Italian soil. He
envisioned “Italy” as a unified entity: “Italy is waiting to see who can be the
one to heal her wounds.”496 As opposed to a more general Christendom,
Machiavelli pictured God caring about Italy itself. Like a mother bird pushing
a baby out of a nest, “God does not want to do everything Himself, and take
away from us our free will and our share of the glory which belongs to us.”497
Machiavelli had no desire to remove God from the equation, though many
commentators accused him of such a purpose.After all,
it was God who created and recognized this thing called “Italy.” Granted,
Machiavelli took numerous shots at the Catholic Church, placing much of the
blame of the fifteenth century wars and discord in Italy on the Church.498 But,
this only served to emphasize the shift he was making from a single, united
Christendom under the Catholic hierarchy to several God-ordained political
units.
Putting his argument
together, Machiavelli advocated a theory of political authority in which God
granted authority to discrete political units or nations, who then passed that
authority on to rulers through institutions. Whether the resulting institutions
were absolutist, constitutionalist, or another variant depended on several
factors, but the theory of political authority remained the same. Machiavelli
clearly stated that a portion of the authority of a ruler came from his own
skill, or the lion and the fox in him. But political authority also derived
from the soundness of the institutions, which were dependent on religion, and
from the appearance of virtuousness. Thus, whether God actually passed
authority on to the political unit or not was unimportant – it was useful to
let the people believe He does. The successful ruler would perpetuate this
belief.
These theories made
Machiavelli a pariah throughout much of the sixteenth century. The Catholics
gave him a place of honor on their Index of Prohibited Books. His work fared no
better among the Protestants as the publication of Anti-Machiavel in 1576 by the
French Calvinist Innocent Gentillet attests. His
image never recovered from the public relations beating that it took, but this
only meant that people did not quote him – they still read him. Even Richelieu,
who embodied a Machiavellian prince in his personal actions and foreign policy,
eschewed association between himself and the Italian theorist. However, many of
the rulers and political theorists of the sixteenth and seventeenth century
paid the ultimate homage to Machiavelli as they began to follow his principles,
all the while appearing to renounce them.
The Proto-nationalism
of Jean Bodin
Jean Bodin published
Six Books of the Republic in 1576, in the closing years of the French Religious
Wars.499 During this period, many groups and persons in France claimed the
right to judge for themselves the validity of political authorities. Bodin responded
with a definition of sovereignty that grew to be the standard definition of the
seventeenth century. Bodin named sovereignty as that indivisible power a state
possessed that stood above question. It was “the most high, absolute, and
perpetual power over the citizens and subjects in a Commonweal.” The entity
within the community that exercised sovereignty could not be lawfully resisted.
The law that compelled this was not man-made, but Natural Law, and hence God’s
Law.
In Bodin’s theory,
authority was passed to men in discrete packages. Bodin did not imagine it
passed directly from God to a ruler, but instead to a Commonwealt,God
used this intermediary because the Commonweal was the location where all of the
disharmonious elements of the universe could be regulated.500 This paralleled
Bodin’s beliefs about the human soul. In his last book, The Theater of Nature,
Bodin described the soul as belonging to both the spiritual and physical
worlds. Thus, the soul acted as an intermediary between these very different
spheres, allowing one to impact the other.501
The “Commonweal” or
nation operated in much the same manner,functioning
as an intermediary between the spiritual world of God and the individuals of
the particular group of people. A Commonweal was as invisible as the soul, but
both were necessary to allow the realms of Heaven and Earth to communicate.
However, temporal stability required that some entity within the Commonweal
must be responsible for wielding the authority God granted to it.502 To Bodin,
the best option was a single person or a monarch. After all, divine authority,
which was perfect, was structured with a single God at the top of all. Bodin
agreed with Divine Right theories that God was all-powerful and, likewise, the
monarch must be absolute. Also, God was merciful and just, and thereby limited
His own power. Like God, Bodin’s monarch is paradoxically absolute and
limited.503 However, Bodin insisted that customary law represented a crucial
limitation on the monarch. Divine Right theorists did not concede such laws
were a limitation.504 For Bodin, customary law emerged from the Commonweal
itself over time and was beyond the power of the monarch to abrogate.505
Tellingly, the staunchly Catholic Bodin supported Protestant Henry of Navarre’s
claims to the throne because French customary law (Salic law) clearly stated
that Henry was next in line.506 Another limitation on the monarch’s “absolute”
power was that, once it was recognized that this person (or possibly group of
persons) possessed sovereignty, the sovereign can neither voluntarily give any
of the power up nor can anyone remove it from him, except God. Thus, with
relatively few limitations, the monarch embodied the Commonweal.
What was presented in
Bodin’s theory was the idea that political authority passed from God to the
Commonweal to the sovereign. However, this last step was extremely subtle.
Because there was no authority in the Commonweal that could withdraw the power
from the sovereign and there was no moment in time when the Commonweal
(whatever that may be) consciously permitted the sovereign to exercise power,
the sovereign and the Commonweal were nearly synonymous. The actions of the
king were the actions of the political community and vice versa. It differed
from earlier theories in that there was the crucial intermediate step of the
Commonweal, but in practical terms it did not differ at all. It shook the
monarch partially loose from allegiance to a universal Christendom and the
foreign policy implications thereof. The monarch must protect his people
spiritually – this was considered nothing new. Yet, he also must physically
protect the Commonweal – a discrete unit – because this unit was the conduit of
sovereign power.
How this power passed
from the Commonweal to the ruler was a mystery. Bodin clearly opposed any
suggestion that the sovereign ruled with the consent of the Commonweal.507
Consent or not, once a sovereign, always the sovereign. William Barclay, who
wrote The Kingdom and the Royal Power in 1600, suggested another possibility.
He promoted an idea known as designation theory, which argued that how
sovereign authority passed to a ruler did not matter; all that mattered was
that once passed it could not be questioned.508 The analogy he used was that of
the Pope. It did not matter if a council of the Church elected him or God
appointed him directly either means was a legitimate way of passing authority
to him. In either case, he ruled only under Christ. Still, although designation
theory absolved the sovereign of accountability, it did not lessen his
responsibility. Thus, Bodin asserted that while the power of the sovereign must
not be resisted, the sovereign must also fulfill his duties to both God and his
Commonweal.
Bodin’s ideas were
extremely influential in late sixteenth and early seventeenth century
France.509 French nobles seeking to ensure that the monarch continued to
respond to their concerns in the Estates General quickly adopted Bodin’s broad
definition of the “republic” or Commonweal.510 This, in turn, significantly
impacted the evolving French political structures and institutions. Thus, the
political vocabulary and institutions in place when Cardinal Richelieu appeared
on the scene were infused with Bodin’s theories on political authority.511
Cardinal Richelieu
It has been charged that
Richelieu cared little for God except where the Almighty could serve his needs.
His motivations matter less, however, than those of his target audiences. He
understood the realities of political authority in early seventeenth-century
France and acted in ways to take advantage of these. His goal was to increase
the authority of the king (and therefore of himself), not to live virtuously.
Whether Richelieu was a devout believer in God or merely a Machiavellian
manipulator of the same, his advice to Louis XIII likely would be the same.For example, Richelieu began the second part of his
Political Testament with a chapter entitled, “The Reign of God the First
Essential,” arguing in part that “princes are expected to establish God’s true
church” within their kingdoms.512 One may interpret this to mean that he was
primarily concerned with the souls of the French, though it would be hard to
find a modern account that asserts this. More importantly, Richelieu knew that
God was a necessary part of any equation of political authority.
The above statement
could be more cynically read to mean that Richelieu urged the king to use his
vast resources to protect a vital tool in the generation of those resources:
the people’s belief. In short, the Cardinal suggested a very Machiavellian strategy
to the Bourbon king. Richelieu then makes a second, less direct, appeal to
God’s credibility. He instructed the king to rule with reason. God implanted
reason in human nature and so to act otherwise was “contrary to Him Who is its
Creator.”513 Because of this, “it is impossible for subjects not to love a
prince if they know that reason is the guide of all his actions.”514 Richelieu
argued that love was a great motivator of obedience. Richelieu had an ulterior
motive in presenting this argument. Louis had a tendency to angry tirades in
front of his court. Richelieu believed these emotional outbursts undermined the
king’s authority, so he prescribed a stoical elevation of reason. Yet, like
Machiavelli, the argument still stressed the primary importance of appearing to
follow the precepts of God. Armed with these ideas and the political influence
to put them into action, Richelieu proceeded to change the practice of foreign
policy in the Continent-wide conflagration now known as the Thirty Years’ War.
Cardinal Richelieu
seized the opportunity to put this political theory into action amidst the
chaos generated during the Thirty Years’ War (1618-1648). Militarily, France’s
principle threat was the greater Habsburg Empire. France’s foreign policy
dilemma revolved around the fact that one of the most potent checks on Habsburg
power consisted of the Protestant heresy within its German territories.
Protecting Catholicism, then, would mean helping the Habsburgs ever more
powerful and threatening. Thus, Richelieu initiated a new foreign policy based
on the idea that the legitimacy of the ruler derived from the French “people,”
which meant that France could now support Protestant forces against the
Catholic Habsburgs without damaging the French monarch’s ability to generate
compliance from the predominantly Catholic French people. This policy proved so
successful that, in order to counter France, other European powers imitated it.
Thus, although the Thirty Years’ War began as a war of religion, by 1635 the
religious motivations for fighting had broken down considerably.
The pretence of a Catholic army fighting a Protestant
foe gave way to national alliances arrayed against one another, crossing
confessional boundaries.
The Thirty Years’ War
The Thirty Years’ War
began as a conflict between Catholic and Protestant. In 1619, the largely
Protestant Bohemian Diet offered its kingship to Protestant Frederick of the
Palatinate. The members of the Diet knew that Frederick’s acceptance would
spark a war, but they believed that Frederick would receive the military
support of his father-in-law, King James I of England. Unfortunately for them,
the Diet and Frederick guessed wrong on this and a number of other issues.
James would likely have aided in the defense against a Catholic invasion into
Protestant territory, but his foreign policy goals did not include Protestant
expansion into Bohemia. The other Protestant nations of Europe were preoccupied
as well: Sweden was bogged down in Poland, while the Dutch Republic nervously
approached the last few months of a twelve-year truce with the Spanish.
Frederick and the Diet also misjudged Protestant unity. Lutheran principalities
did not come to the assistance of the Calvinist Frederick. Lutheran John George
of Saxony even sent his troops to fight with the Emperor after receiving
concessions targeted at Lutherans alone. Lacking allies, Frederick and the
Bohemians were easily defeated by Imperial forces near White Mountain in 1620.
Thus, religious motivations produced this spark that flamed into the Thirty
Years’ War.
A common
interpretation of this period is that these Wars were about politics, not
religion. The evidence demonstrates that not only is this incorrect, it is a
false dichotomy: religion and politics were inseparable. The Holy Roman Empire
had already divided itself into two camps following the 1555 Peace of Augsburg.
These camps solidified their alliances in the Protestant Union of 1608 and the
Catholic Union of 1609. The solution of the Peace of Augsburg converted every
change in political leadership into a religious question: Cuius
regio eius religio (Whose region, his religion).
Since the Bohemian king also was one of the seven electors of the Empire every
ruler in the Holy Roman Empire had a stake in whether the next king of Bohemia
was the Catholic Archduke Ferdinand or the Protestant Frederick. The Bohemians
had elected Catholic Archduke Ferdinand of Styria as their king in 1617. As a
result, the Imperial Electors were split 4-3 Catholic. When Ferdinand refused
to meet the religious guarantees the Calvinist Bohemian Diet requested, they
replaced him with the Protestant Frederick, shifting the balance of the
electors in favor of the Protestants. Ferdinand was elected as Holy Roman
Emperor a few days later, but his election was questioned legally since he
technically no longer held the right to cast a vote for himself. Thus, while
there were many political and economic causes for the Wars, they could not be
separated from the basic religious confrontation.515
While Protestants in
the Empire and throughout Europe refused to assist an expansion into Bohemia,
they quickly responded to Catholic expansion into the Protestant Palatinate.
Archduke Ferdinand’s Jesuit advisors had inspired him to vow to eradicate heresy
in his lands.516 Once he became Emperor Ferdinand II, the power at his disposal
increased enormously. The Emperor captured Heidelberg in 1622, transferring one
of the Protestant elector votes to the Catholics. The Catholics now solidly
controlled the Electoral Diet. The tenuous balance created in 1555 had been
destroyed. Even Catholic princes grew wary of the new power Emperor Ferdinand
II possessed.517 Although this cautiousness did not blossom into outright
resistance, it hindered the Habsburgs’ ability to deal a final blow to
Protestantism. The European Protestants, for their part, organized in the
summer of 1624. The Dutch Republic, England, and Denmark signed an alliance
against the Habsburgs. The Danish king saw Sweden and the Dutch Republic as his
greatest military threats; nevertheless, he set this dispute aside to oppose
the growing dominance of the Counter-Reformation in the Empire.518 Once again
ideological threats trumped physical ones and all the powers of Europe lined up
behind their confessions. All, that is, except one.
The irony was that
Cardinal Richelieu of Catholic France engineered this new European Protestant
alliance. His foreign policy undermined the simplicity of the religious
bifurcation. He pursued the interests of France first and foremost. With the
Huguenot problem firmly in hand, the greatest threat to France was not
Protestantism, but a powerful Spain that could only grow more powerful without
the constant distraction of conflict in the Empire. Although Richelieu’s
Protestant alliance fell apart in 1626 thanks to the military successes of
Wallenstein, he had given the Protestants sufficient time to recover from the
initial defeats of the war and for Sweden to enter the war in opposition to the
Habsburgs. France benefited from a Catholic-Protestant stalemate: this kept
Protestantism from spreading and it prevented the Habsburgs from gaining
absolute powers.
The old habits of the
early sixteenth-century reemerged as France and Spain again fought over control
of northern Italy. In 1624, France began an unsuccessful campaign to wrestle
control of the Valtelline Passes through the Alps
away from Spain. In 1627, fighting broke out again when the duke of Mantua died
without a male heir. Spain besieged Casale where the French candidate was holed
up. After a delay in which Richelieu took La Rochelle back from the Huguenots,
France relieved Casale, driving back the Spanish. The Pope stepped in and
arranged a truce, arguing that two Catholic powers should not fight when the
real enemy was heresy. Many in France shared his perspective, believing that
Richelieu’s policy was both strategically wrong and morally evil. However, in
October 1630, on the Day of Dupes, King Louis XIII settled the question
in favor of Richelieu, legitimating his policy and increasing his authority
within the government.
How could Richelieu
follow such a foreign policy and not simultaneously undermine the legitimacy of
Louis XIII? If the King’s authority came directly from God maintaining
legitimacy would have been difficult. After all, his policy supported heretics
and religious allies of the hated Huguenots. However, Richelieu created a large
propaganda machine designed to persuade crucial segments of the population that
authority passed through the nation, the “French,” an entity recognized and
created by God.519 Thus, the monarch’s job included protecting “France,” a
divine thing as valuable and as “holy” as the Catholic Church. From this
perspective, Richelieu was not promoting Protestant heresy, but defending the
chosen nation of God. Hence, his innovative political theory allowed for a new
foreign policy that proved to be incredibly successful.
The specific
conditions of in the early stages of the Thirty Years’ War permitted the
Protestants to justify working with Richelieu. After all, France’s territorial
concern was not northern Germany but northern Italy, and Protestants everywhere
could delight in the spectacle of Catholics fighting it out in the Pope’s
backyard. Plus, the Protestants honestly needed the help; they were in real
danger of being wiped out of Germany. The Protestants could accept the
physical presence of soldiers from Protestant Sweden, while Richelieu and
Catholic France merely paid the bills, but supplied no troops. The Swedish king
Gustavus Adolphus, for his part, envisioned himself as the deliverer of the
Protestants from the persecuting Catholics.520 That France backed his army
financially was less important than the ultimate goal of rescuing Calvinism.
Once the larger
Protestant forces of the Dutch Republic and Sweden entered the fray, the
Habsburgs once again faced a stalemate in their lands. This, rather than
victory for one side or the other, was Richelieu’s intent. Thus, for several
years France remained comfortably behind the scenes in the larger
Catholic-Protestant struggle. The Swedes signed an agreement with Richelieu in
1631 in which they would supply the men for an army, while France would pay for
much of the fighting for the next five years.521 At this stage, France was the
only state pursuing a foreign policy linked to nation rather than religion.
Imitators of Richelieu’s Policies
France’s monopoly on
this particular foreign policy changed over the course of the war. One of the
earliest examples was Savoy, a duchy in northern Italy that had been the center
of the conflict between the French and the Habsburgs for nearly a century and a
half. Savoy’s very existence depended on what historian Toby Osborne has called
“diplomatic pragmatism,” which was another way of saying that the
Savoyard dukes in the early stages of the Thirty Years War pursued a foreign
policy based on “national” interests over the interests of Catholicism.522 Like
France, the dukes’ survival depended on controlling the power of the Habsburgs,
even if that meant alliances with Protestant powers. Thus, Savoyard foreign
policy appeared incredibly erratic as the dukes alternately allied with France
and plotted Richelieu’s death, all “as circumstances and pragmatism
required.”523
The major powers of
Europe recognized the strategic value of imitating France’s foreign policy more
slowly. The death of the Swedish king Gustavus at Lutzen in 1632 and the
crushing Protestant defeat at Nordlingen in 1635,
greatly reduced the power of the major Protestant leaders. Sweden began to
scale back on its commitments in Germany. Richelieu found that, to check the
Habsburgs, France could no longer merely play the role of behind-the-scenes
financial backer. Hence, Richelieu formed two new alliances in 1635, one with
Sweden and one with the Dutch Republic. In each of these French troops and
money would actively support the war efforts against Spain, in particular, and
her allies. Although French troops had relatively few successes in the field
(as Richelieu would lament in his Testament), the French spent money
effectively in hiring mercenaries and preventing mutinies among the Swedish
army. In terms of military organization, 1635 was a “turning point” in France
as state appointed intendants began to coordinate much of the logistics,
thereby centralizing authority.524 For the most part, France’s Protestant
allies could accept this new situation with a clean conscience: the enemy
remained Catholicism.525
However, Richelieu’s
new style of foreign policy did not go unnoticed for long. The policy was
relatively successful and could only be countered with a similar approach. Many
German Protestants began to argue that if they were going to fight side-by-side
with Catholics anyway, it should be with fellow Germans rather than
Frenchmen.526 Among the Catholic Germans there existed a thorough understanding
of the implications of Richelieu’s policies, having been the victims of them
for a decade and a half. Spanish Chancellor Olivares understandably distrusted
the “Catholic Peace” the Pope brokered in 1630 and had since been preparing
Spain for an offensive war against France.527 Emperor Ferdinand also recognized
that if the Empire faced internal religious divisions and France did not, it
was clear who would emerge in the stronger position. Thus, sufficient
incentives existed among both German Protestants and Catholics to pursue
negotiations designed to set aside religious differences and present a national
front against “foreign” powers. In the Treaty of Prague, May 1635, the Emperor
promised to suspend several of his anti-Protestant policies instituted during
the war and the Protestant princes (who had not been bought off by Richelieu)
agreed to help reclaim territory taken by invaders.528
Within a few months,
German Catholics and Protestants together turned on the Protestant Swedish
armies and their Catholic French allies in northern Germany.This
new development forced Sweden to adjust its justification for war in
Germany.529 Sweden had entered the war using theological arguments, principally
the persecution of fellow Protestants. Whatever the additional economic and
strategic advantages Gustavus hoped to gain, it was the theological
justifications that had been sold to the Swedish people and nobles. After 1635,
however, Sweden found itself allied with and supplied by Catholic France,
fighting against German armies that contained Protestants. The theological
arguments began to lose their effectiveness.As a
result, justifications back home morphed into an argument resembling a modernday“police action.” Sweden was forced to come to
terms with Richelieu’s new style of foreign policy and adjust its own arguments
of authority accordingly, even though this meant a reduction in credibility in
Sweden.
To a lesser extent,
Richelieu’s foreign policy spread to areas at the very fringes of the war.
Scotland, for example, developed a stronger sense of national feeling as a
result of the war.530 Although predominantly Catholic through much of the sixteenthcentury, it had undergone a Presbyterian
Reformation. The Presbyterians were in ascendancy as their King, James
VI, had also been crowned James I of England. It was his daughter, Elizabeth,
wife of Frederick of the Palatinate, who had been “dishonored” by the Catholics
in the opening stages of the war in 1620. Scottish Protestants had turned out
in droves for the war effort on the continent and were considered highly valued
troops in both the Swedish and Dutch armies. But, even Scottish Catholics in
the highlands were incensed at this effrontery to the Scottish Elizabeth. The
changes brought about in 1635 provided the opportunity for all loyal Scots,
regardless of confession, to fight against the Empire. France created brigades
in its forces in which Scottish Catholics could defend the honor of their
“favorite daughter.” Here, at last, was a foreign policy goal that all “Scots”
could unite behind.
Even the “soldiers”
of the Counter-Reformation, the Jesuits, recognized the changing winds and
adjusted their actions accordingly.531 Muzio Vitelleschi,
the Superior General of the Order from 1615 to 1645, had consistently urged the
Jesuit confessors in royal courts throughout Europe to avoid acting as
political advisors. He recognized that the survival of the Society of Jesus
depended on the support of princes and kings. When a Jesuit became embroiled in
politics, he necessarily made enemies within the court. In 1638, Nicholas
Caussin, Louis XIII’s Jesuit confessor, learned this lesson when he supported
the noble faction that wanted to make peace with the Habsburgs against
Protestants. Richelieu systematically decimated this group, forcing Caussin out
of France. In order to continue the Jesuit mission in France, Vitelleschi ordered Caussin’s successor to submit any and
all moral and political issues to Richelieu. In a bow to Richelieu’s
Gallicanism, the Superior General even forbade Jesuits from writing on the
supremacy of the Pope. The letters of Vitelleschi to
the Jesuit confessors throughout Europe demonstrated that he understood a
change had taken place in 1635 – the Catholic princes were far more open to
allying with Protestants.532 Vitelleschi ordered the
Jesuits to remain aloof of even this seemingly heretical turn of events and
focus their energies entirely on the spiritual needs of their royal charges.
Though the war
continued for another twelve years, a change in the definition of “we” was
taking place in Germany. This should not be overblown: religion remained
incredibly important to the people, but because the fighting no longer involved
the extermination of heresy or the freedom of religious practice, it could be
partially set aside in anticipation of peace. In addition, though we can talk
about the “German” nation today, the concept would have been hard to pin down
during the war. A somewhat shared culture had existed for many centuries and
the devastation the war caused in the territories served to fuse the sense of
“we” more strongly, yet the same influences applied to the individual
principalities as well. No force within the Empire actively sought to fuse the
various “national” tendencies into a single German movement and, in fact, many
forces fought against such a move, in particular the princes. However, this
does not negate the fact that there was a fundamental redefinition of why
people fought and suffered. Protestantism could eventually be freely practiced
in Saxony, for example, but only after the fighting was concluded.
The Peace of Westphalia 1648
By the 1640s, a new
theory of political authority dominated the European landscape. Authority
devolved to the ruler from God through a discrete bundle that was alternately
called the “commonwealth,” “republic,” “people,” or “nation.” While not
divorcing itself wholly from the three confessions that constituted the sources
of transcendent credibility of the sixteenth century, rulers and people
increasingly tended to focus on the nation as the source of political authority
rather than the confession. As a result, the number of sources of transcendent
credibility in Europe increased. At the very least, every major power emerging
from the War considered its nation a separate source of transcendent
credibility. A stable resolution to the War therefore required a political
solution that recognized the new reality of “proto-nationalism.” In particular,
far more distinctive boundaries were needed between political units of
differing sources of transcendent credibility. For any peace to be stable, the
European powers also had to develop rules regarding the mutual recognition of
these borders and other issues involving territorial integrity. This became the
key agenda at the multiyear talks that culminated in the Peace of Westphalia in
1648.
The Peace of
Westphalia returned to the 1555 Peace of Augsburg for a solution. At Augsburg,
it had been decided that whatever religion the ruler of a territory was,
Lutheran or Catholic, the people of the territory must be as well.
Persons who found themselves
in a territory embracing a different religion could emigrate to a more
appropriate principality. Augsburg succeeded in keeping a tenuous peace in the
Empire for more than half a century. It ultimately fell apart for two reasons.
First, it did not foresee the success of Calvinism. Augsburg did not allow for
just any state religion, but only Lutheranism and Catholicism. Calvinism thus
posed a threat to both recognized parties. However, over the course of the
Thirty Years’ War, Lutherans and Calvinists began to unify their efforts
against the common enemy of Catholicism.533 This made it easier to include
Calvinists in any new settlement. The Peace of Augsburg also collapsed due to
the popular strategy of replacing the prince of a territory with a prince of
the other religion as a means of rooting out heresy in the Empire. This led to
countless intrigues and conspiracies among the princes of Germany and
contributed to the destabilization of the Empire. Negotiators knew that if the
1648 peace were to last, significant adjustments would need to be made to the
Peace of Augsburg.534
These adjustments
produced new international rules of behavior. The conferees at Westphalia
started with the basic Augsburg formula, but added Calvinism as a legitimate
third option for the ruler of a territory. This solved the immediate problem,
but it was a far cry from suggesting that Westphalia resulted in religious
toleration. As Historian John Coffey argues, “The Treaty of Westphalia did not
stop the enforcement of uniformity within particular territories, it simply
signaled an end to confessional wars between different states.”535 Lutherans
who woke up in a Catholic principality still had to emigrate to practice their
religion. The Treaty also accorded “territorial superiority . . . in
matters ecclesiastical as well as political” to the princes within the Holy
Roman Empire.536 A political arrangement based on territoriality necessarily
meant that a good deal of the remainder of the settlement’s text would involve
exactly which prince would be superior in which territory. One common
misconception about Westphalia is that it instituted the notion of
“sovereignty.”
However, although the
German princes were superior in their territory and they could form foreign
alliances without the Emperor’s approval, the settlement clearly stated that
the actions and alliances of the princes’ could not be used against the Empire or
Emperor. Hence, the princes were not “sovereign” in any absolute sense, even
though they possessed some sovereign powers. In short, the new
proto-nationalism produced a “proto-sovereignty.” Proto-sovereignty
necessitated more distinctive boundaries between political units. Territorial
superiority was not a gift bestowed but a right to be protected. The boundaries
listed in the Peace of Westphalia became focal points at which one ruler’s
authority began and another’s ended. The militaries of non-major powers that
had been designed to fight within larger armies alongside other principalities
were now reformed to be more self-sufficient and to protect their own borders.
More powerful political units, such as the Austrian Habsburgs and France,
created militaries that could both attack and defend. These reforms in support
of more distinctive borders were enhanced by the fact that political units that
could afford it frequently hired foreign mercenaries who brought significant
expertise to the changing armies.537
The settlement of
Westphalia did not bring a utopian peace to Europe, but it did provide many of
the smaller political units (especially within the Empire) with sufficient
space and time to capitalize on their newfound proto-sovereign powers.
Westphalia was just a
peace of paper with no enforcement mechanisms so to
speak. Still, at least in Germany, the exhaustion of the War enabled the Peace
to be selfenforcing. For the most part,
principalities left one another alone to rebuild what was destroyed and to
consolidate their power in their respective territories. The princes took
advantage of this with enhanced hierarchical judicial systems, the minting of
coins of more determinate value than those circulating during the War, and the
licensing of new mints under strict government control. However, it was
difficult to establish national currencies during this period. Germany had been
the international meeting place for soldiers from every land for the past three
decades, which meant that there was a tremendous amount of foreign currency
still in circulation. Thus, the idea that “market forces were more powerful
than the coercive power of early modern rulers” must be balanced with the fact
that, despite these difficulties and costs, early modern rulers kept trying to
set up national currencies.538 In sum, the boundaries between political units
grew relatively more distinct in this period, although at least in the Empire
they were still far from a modern conception of a distinctive border.
Many scholars have
argued that Westphalia’s primacy of place in the study of modern international
relations has been overdone.539 I would contend that such an argument is true
if one is looking to Westphalia as a moment in which real sovereignty became the
core principle of international relations practice. Westphalia was only a
reflection of practices and beliefs that had begun to emerge during the War,
first with France and soon imitated by other European powers. If a moment of
change is demanded, two moments in particular stand out. First, the loose
Protestant alliance Richelieu cobbled together in 1624 signaled a change in
foreign policy as it had been practiced since Martin Luther. Second, the year
1635 brought France directly into the war effort in Germany and the Treaty of
Prague united German Catholics and Protestants together against invaders. This
Treaty was recognition that the rules of the game had changed – rulers now
shifted to generating compliance using protonationalism
rather than a confession. The Treaty of Westphalia in 1648 merely codified
these new realities of inter-polity relations.
Westphalia also
disappoints those who want to see it as the birthplace of the true sovereignty
associated with the modern nation-state. The idea that it was the start of the
modern nation-states system has taken many hits recently, and I would tend to
agree with the modern critics.540 However, I also would argue that it did
institutionalize a system that was an evolutionary stage between the systems of
the sixteenth century and the system of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
It represented the beginnings of sovereignty, rather than sovereignty itself.
Hence, if Westphalia was not a moment of change, it was the background in which
important changes were occurring. It marked the period in which rulers began to
put new ways of thinking about legitimacy into practice.
So in any case, the
complex religious clauses of the [Westphalian] settlement were a modus vivendi
that enabled Protestants and Catholics to coexist in an age in which they cared
less and less about the uniform establishment of their faith.541 And the above
has demonstrated that the reason why the sixteenth century dominance of
confessions became less important was the adoption of protonationalist
ideas on political authority during the Thirty Years’ War. France adopted this
theory because Cardinal Richelieu believed that the minimal costs in compliance
that resulted from the slight change in the source of transcendent credibility
would be far outweighed by the benefits of the foreign policy that
proto-nationalism now made permissible. Other European powers adopted this same
proto-nationalist theory because France had demonstrated how effective it could
be and because it was the only means to counter France’s growing power. The
change in sources of transcendent credibility was subtle, but the effects were
enormous. God still held the position of prominence as ultimate source of
political authority and legitimacy, yet because this power now passed through
the “nation” and the ruler was the physical embodiment of that nation, the
ruler could openly act in the interest of his realm rather than in the name of
Christendom or orthodox belief.
Conclusion of P.6
The adoption of
proto-nationalism increased the number of sources of transcendent credibility
as each major power, at the very least, saw political authority passing from
God to ruler through a different nation. However, as the Peace of Westphalia
made clear, this change was very subtle for two main reasons. First, God was
still a crucial part of the proto-nationalist formula. Therefore, rulers still
had to be aware of the religious questions within their territory and
throughout Europe. The pursuit of national interest was not unlimited (hence,
proto-nationalism). Second, at least within the Holy Roman Empire, princes
continued to rule under the nominal sovereignty of the Emperor. Granted, they
received many sovereign-like powers, yet they still lacked true sovereignty.
Thus, in many ways they functioned as sovereigns within their territory, but on
major matters of state, the Emperor and the Imperial institutions dominated (in
theory, if not in practice). Thus, the system instituted in Westphalia was something
very different from that which preceded it and that which would eventually
follow it.
Since
proto-nationalism increased the number of sources of transcendent credibility,
this created a situation in which a political unit’s security depended on
investment in more distinctive boundaries. Within the Holy Roman Empire,
however, boundaries between principalities were relatively more distinctive,
but not as distinctive as would be the case for other major European powers who
possessed powers approaching that of modern-day sovereignty. We may today call
this protosovereignty, knowing with the advantage of
hindsight that a far more developed form of sovereignty would follow over the
course of the next century. However, in 1648, these changes would have appeared
incredibly significant in themselves producing boundaries that, when compared
with the earlier century, were quite distinctive. Proto-nationalism and
proto-sovereignty enjoyed a reciprocal relationship: the growing acceptance of
one enhanced the acceptance of the other and vice versa. Thus,
proto-nationalism should not be considered an instance of punctuated
equilibrium in the evolution of international systems. From its inception, it
tended to move toward a system in which “nationalism” and “sovereignty” were
the norms. The story of why and how this occurred and the effects of this
change are the subjects of the next and final part.
448 See Adam J Lerner
(1991), “Transcendence of the Nation: National Identity and the Terrain of the
Divine,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 20(3): 407-27; Hertmut Lehmann (1991), “The Germans as a Chosen People:
Old Testament Themes in German Nationalism,” German Studies Review 14(2):
261-73; Dale VanKley (1991), “Protestantism, Catholicism, and the Religious
Origins of the French and American Revolutions,” Fides et Historia 23(1):
53-68; AJ Hoover (1987), “Religion and National Stereotypes: A German
Protestant Example,” History of European Ideas 8(3): 297-307; Bo Andersson
(1999), “Sweden, the Elect Nation,” Lutheran Quarterly 13(3): 305-14.
449 “God alone
chooses, he alone confirms . . . . Neither those who are now called ‘electors,’nor others who in whatever way have been so
called, should be given this name; rather they should be thought of as
‘proclaimers of divine providence,’” Dante (1996 [1314]), Monarchy, Prue Shaw,
ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 93.
453 The
revitalization of the Catholic Church in the mid-sixteenth century enabled this
theory to experience a brief renaissance. Toward the end of the 1500s, several
Jesuits in Spain argued that God gave the Pope authority to judge secular
rulers. Foremost among this group was Francisco Suarez who reasoned that,
although security and order on earth are important, God ordained that the
spiritual purpose of man was far more important. Just as God subordinated
secular goals to spiritual goals, likewise, Christ made his “Vicar pastor over
Christian princes no less than over the rest of Christendom, Francisco Suarez
(1612), A Treatise on the Laws and God the Lawgiver, quoted in WM Spellman
(1998), European Political Thought 1600-1700 (New York: St. Martin’s Press):
47.
454 Georges Duby
(1980), The Three Orders: Feudal Society Imagined (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press): 13-64.
455 Although both
ruler and nobility relied on the same source of transcendent credibility, there
remained crucial differences between the ruler and the nobles, for example, the
ruler’s divine ability to heal scrofula with a touch, EH Kantorowicz (1957),
The King’s Two Bodies (Princeton: Princeton
University Press).
456 See Hendrik Spruyt (1994), The Sovereign State and Its Competitors
(Princeton: Princeton University Press): 34-57.
457 Yves Charles
Zarka (1999), “The Foundations of Natural Law,” British Journal for the History
of Philosophy 7(1): 15-32.
458 Stephen M Fallon
(1988), “‘To Act or Not To Act:’ Milton’s Conception of Divine Freedom,”
Journal of the History of Ideas 49(3): 425-53.
459 The debate on the
distinction between “absolute” and “ordained” power of God and the parallel
with rulers is most thoroughly discussed by the medievalist Francis Oakley,
especially (1998), “The Absolute and Ordained Power of God and King in the
Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries: Philosophy, Science, Politics, and Law,”
Journal of the History of Ideas 59(4): 669-690.
460 Thomas Aquinas
(1961 [13th century]), “On Kingship,” in Michael Curtis, ed., The Great
Political Theories, Volume I (New York: Avon Books): 197.
461 Ibid., 198.
462 These two
questions must be considered together. According to seventeenth century Divine
Right theorists, the king could not make laws without the consent of the
people. However, if the monarch did violate this principle, he could not be
resisted. Thus, the ruler had responsibilities, but no
accountability to the people, Glenn Burgess (1992), “The Divine Right of Kings
Reconsidered,” English Historical Review 107(425): 837-61.
463 SW Haas (1980),
“Martin Luther’s ‘Divine Right’ Kingship and the Royal Supremacy: Two Tracts from
the 1531 Parliament and Convocation of the Clergy,” Journal of Ecclesiastical
History 31(3): 317-27; Haas (1979), “Henry VIII’s Glasse of Truth,” History
64(212): 353-62.
464 James I (1961
[1598]), “The Trew Law of Free Monarchies,” in Michael Curtis, ed., The Great
Political Theories, Volume I (New York: Avon Books): 282.
465 Ibid.
466 James I (1961
[1609]), “Speech of 1609,” in The Great Political Theories, Volume I: 285.
467 Ibid.
468 James I (1961
[1616]), “Speech in Star Chamber,” in The Great Political Theories, Volume I:
286-87.
469 Infallibility
served as a check on the Pope because the current Pope was constrained by the
decrees of his equally infallible predecessors, Brian Tierney (1971), “The
Origins of Papal Infallibility,” Journal of Ecumenical Studies 8(4): 841-64.
470 Although the
overwhelming number of sixteenth century authors who advocated the right of the
people to resist were Protestant, the Catholics also had a number, especially
among the Spanish Jesuits, that advocated resistance to a tyrant and even in some
cases assassination. Advocating mediated authority, the Jesuit priest Juan de
Mariana asserted, “Assuredly the republic, whence the regal power has its
source, can call a king into court . . . [and] it can strip him of his
principate,’ Juan de Mariana (1948 [1599]), The King and the Education of the
King, George Albert Moore, ed. (Washington: Country Dollar Press): chapter 8.
Many Catholics also still adhered to the Medieval version of resistance: the
Pope had the authority to call for the resistance of a king.
471 Christopher
Goodman (1972 [1558]), How Superior Powers Ought to be Obeyed of Their Subjects
(New York: Da Capo Press); Dan G Danner (1981), “Resistance and the Ungodly
Magistrate in the Sixteenth Century: The Marian Exiles,” Journal of the
American Academy of Religion 49(3): 471-81.
472 “I say, it is not
only lawful to punish to the death such as labour to
subvert the true religion, but the magistrates and people are bound to so to do
unless they will provoke the wrath of God against themselves. And therefore I
fear not to affirm that it had been the duty of the nobility, judges, rulers
and people of England not only to have resisted and againstanded
Mary that Jezebel whom they call their queen, but also to have punished her to
death, with all the sort of her idolatrous priests,” John Knox (1994 [1558]),
“An Appellation to the Nobility and Estates of Scotland,” On Rebellion, Roger A
Mason, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 104.
473 Buchanan wrote
his Dialogue on the Law of Kingship among the Scots in the 1550s while in
exile, but the book was published posthumously in 1579, coinciding with the
publication of several Calvinist tracts that promoted the same basic (though
less radical) theory of resistance. Buchanan specifically stated that each
individual had the authority to lawfully assassinate a bad ruler: “A tyrant
hath not only no just authority over a people, but is also their enemy . . . .
A lawful war being once undertaken with an enemy, and for a just cause, it is
lawful not only for the whole people to kill that enemy, but for every one of
them,” George Buchanan (2004 [1579]), A Dialogue on the Law of Kingship among
the Scots: A Critical Edition and Translation of George Buchanan’s De Iure Regni apud Scotos Dialogus (St. Andrew’s Studies in Reformation History
Series) (Aldershot: Ashgate). Ironically, Buchanan served as a tutor for Mary
Queen of Scots, Michel Montaigne, and James VI of Scotland (later James I of
England). James did not have pleasant memories of his tutor.
474 For example,
Richard Hooker (1989 [1593]), Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity, Arthur
Stephen McGrade, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press); Thomas Smith
(1565), De Republica Anglorum.
475 Huguenots often
claimed they were fighting for the purpose of defending the king and his
estate, Kathleen A Parrow (1991), “Neither Treason Nor Heresy: Use of Defense
Arguments to Avoid Forfeiture during the French Wars of Religion,” Sixteenth
Century Journal 22(4): 705-16.
476 Luc Racaut (2002), “Religious Polemic and Huguenot
Self-Perception and Identity, 1554-1619,” in Raymond A Mentzer and Andrew
Spicer, eds., Society and Culture in the Huguenot World,1559-1685 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press): 29-43.
477 According to
Julian H Franklin it was probably written by Philippe de Mornay; Julian H
Fraklin, ed. (1969), Constitutionalism and Resistance in the Sixteenth Century:
Three Treatises by Hotman, Beza, and Mornay (New
York: Pegasus): 39.
478 “Vindiciae Contra Tyrannos,” in
Michael Curtis, ed., The Great Political Theories, Volume I (New York: Avon
Books, 1961): 255-56.
479 Ibid., 256
(emphasis added).
480 Theodore de Beza,
the most influential post-Calvin theologian among the Huguenots, probably
inspired this limitation. In 1574, he wrote that the Romans 13 command of
obedience to government applied locally. Thus, when the king violated the
rights of the local magistrates, usually Huguenots, these magistrates were
justified in resisting, deposing, and killing the king and in calling the
populace to assist in this work, Scott M Manetsch (2000), Theodore Beza and the
Quest for Peace in France, 1572-1598 (Leiden: Brill). Also see Theodore de Beza
(1969 [1574]), “Right of Magistrates,” in Constitutionalism and Resistance in
the Sixteenth Century: 101-35.
481 Antony Black
(1992), Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press): 19-20.
482 John of Paris
(1988 [1302-03]), “On the Origin and Nature of Government in Church and State,”
in Tierney, The Crisis of Church and State: 208.
483 Recent historical
scholarship has attacked the traditional concept of absolutism, pointing out in
particular that no monarch can rule without at least some form of consent,
Richard Bonney (1987), “Absolutism: What’s In a Name?” French History 1(1): 93-117;
William Beik (1990), “The Culture of Protest in Seventeenth-Century French
Towns,” Social History 15(1): 1-23; Nicholas Henshall (1992), “The Myth of
Absolutism,” History Today 42: 40-47; John Rogister
(1996), “Some New Directions in the Historiography of State Assemblies and
Parliaments in Early and Late Modern Europe,” Parliaments, Estates and
Representation 16: 1-16; William Beik (2005), “The Absolutism of Louis XIV as
Social Collaboration,” Past and Present 188(1): 195-224. One example of this is
that a king or duke who raised taxes without summoning the parliamentary body
still usually activated informal channels of advise
and consent with key lesser nobles and burghers, Matthew Vester (2000), “Fiscal
Commissions, Consensus and Informal Representation: Taxation in the Savoyard
Domains, 1559-1580,” Parliaments, Estates and Representation 20: 59-74. A
parallel argument concerning the non-absolute nature of absolutism within the
Catholic Church during the Counter-Reformation can be found in Barbara B
Diefendorf (2004), “Contradictions of the Century of Saints: Aristocratic
Patronage and the Convents of Counter-Reformation Paris,” French Historical
Studies 24(3): 469-99. Thus, absolutism was never absolute, Hilton Root (1989),
“Tying the King’s Hands: Credible Commitments and Royal Fiscal Policy During
the Old Regime,” Rationality and Society 1(2): 240-58. Absolutism as a
definitional term may be misleading, yet it remains a useful signifier of a
type of political authority that existed in the early modern period and should
not be discarded. At the very least, absolutism can be seen as the monarch’s
struggle “to move in the direction of greater independence without ever
achieving complete freedom of action,” JS Morrill (1978), “French Absolutism as
Limited Monarchy,” Historical Journal 21(4): 961-72. The private nature of
informal networks provided the monarch greater independence than the more
public formal institutions of assemblies. Thus, the distinction between
absolutism and constitutionalism may be seen as reliance on formal versus
informal institutions of representatives of the people.
484 Quoted in Richard
S Dunn (1979), The Age of Religious Wars, 1559-1715 (New York:WW
Norton and Company): 181-82.
485 Yoram Barzel (2002), A Theory of the State: Economic Rights,
Legal Rights, and the Scope of the State (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press): 138-54.
486 Francisco de
Vitoria (1991 [1539]), “On the American Indians,” in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds., Political Writings
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 231-92.
487 Two conditions in
particular made the success of the third mechanism inevitable. First, as God
was replaced by the more secular idea of the nation as the source of
transcendent credibility, the first mechanism became ineffective. Second, the
development of Westphalian notions of sovereignty (also a consequence of the
success of the idea of the nation as the source of transcendent credibility)
increasingly rendered the second mechanism irrelevant. Thus, the third
mechanism and the political ideas that necessarily accompanied it achieved
dominance in Europe.
488 In his
Reflections, Edmund Burke would argue that any social contract was superseded
by “the great primeval contract of eternal society, linking the lower with the
higher natures, connecting the visible and invisible world, according to a
fixed compact sanctioned by the inviolable oath which holds all physical and
all moral natures each in their appointed place” and which depends on the
divine
“Institutor and Author and Protector of civil society.” Quoted in Don Herzog
(1998), Poisoning the Minds of the Lower Orders (Princeton: Princeton
University Press): 34.
489 While a
transition to a “French proto-nation” as the source of transcendent credibility
entailed several benefits for the government, there is still a question of why
the French people went along with it. First, the French proto-nation would have
been consistently linked to Catholic Christianity, so in large part, there
would have been few instances where old beliefs would have been contradicted
outright. Second, the French Catholic Church had a long history of distancing
itself from the larger Catholic Church (a phenomenon known as Gallicanism), JHM
Salmon (1991), “Catholic Resistance Theory, Ultramontanism, and Royalist
Response, 1580-1620,” in JH Burns, ed., The Cambridge History of Political
Thought, 1450-1700 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 231-33. Thus, the
average French subject would have been less surprised than other European
Catholics to find the leaders of their respective proto-nation increasingly
distancing it from the larger European Catholic community. Third, “reason of
state” theories were increasingly used in France since the late sixteenth
century in response to the civil wars in France, Nannerl
Keohane (1980), Philosophy and the State in France: Renaissance to
Enlightenment (Princeton: Princeton University Press): chs.
4-5. French subjects would therefore have been somewhat familiar with the
vocabulary used by protonationalism. Fourth,
Richelieu invested heavily in authors, artists, and scholars who were paid to
produce propaganda that helped the new proto-nationalism to appear legitimate
and natural [see below]. These four reasons suggest why the French subjects
went along with the transition to the degree that they did, at least in the
beginning.
490 See, for example,
Montesquieu, Vico, and Hegel.
491 DE Luscombe and GR
Evans (1988), “The Twelfth-Century Renaissance,” in JH Burns, ed., The
Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c. 350 – c. 1450 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press): 323-25.
492 Erasmus (1997
[1516]), The Education of a Christian Prince, Lisa Jardine, ed. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press): 2.
493 Quentin Skinner
(2000 [1981]), Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford
University Press): 70-72.
494 Nicolo
Machiavelli (1970 [1514]), The Discourses, Bernard Crick, ed. (New York:
Penguin Books): 139.
495 Ibid., 141.
496 Nicolo
Machiavelli (1961 [1513]), The Prince, George Bull, ed. (New York: Penguin
Books): 134.
497 Ibid., 135.
498 The Discourses:
Book I, Chapter 12.
499 Jean Bodin
(1992), On Sovereignty, Julian H Franklin, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press).
500 David Parker
(1981), “Law, Society, and the State in the Thought of Jean Bodin,” History of
Political Thought 2(2): 253-85.
501 Ann Blair (1997),
The Theater of Nature: Jean Bodin and Renaissance Science (Princeton: Princeton
University Press): 137-42.
502 Daniel Engster (1996), “Jean Bodin, Scepticism
and Absolute Sovereignty,” History of Political Thought 17(4): 469-99.
503 Parker (1981),
“Law, Society, and the State in the Thought of Jean Bodin.”
504 James I argued
that the Chancery Court, “his own court of conscience,” stood above customary
law in England (common law), Mark Fortier (1998), “Equity and Ideas: Coke,
Ellesmere, and James I,” Renaissance Quarterly 51(4): 1255-81.
505 JHM Salmon
(1996), “The Legacy of Jean Bodin: Absolutism, Populism, or Constitutionalism,”
History of Political Thought 17(4): 500-22.
506 Paul Lawrence
Rose (1978), “Bodin and the Bourbon Succession to the French Throne,
1583-1594,” Sixteenth Century Journal 9(2): 75-98.
507 This made Bodin’s
theory very different from the theories of political authority being produced
by the Huguenots in the same era. JHM Salmon (1973), “Francois Hotman and Jean Bodin: The Dilemma of Sixteenth-Century
French Constitutionalism,” History Today 23(11): 801-09. 450 “It must be held .
. . that God permits those assembled in a general council, in defining a
question of faith and in other matters, to proceed according to their
intelligence, assisted by the general divine influence. It is therefore
conceded that it is not possible for a general council to err,” William of
Ockham (1995 [1347]), “A Dialogue, Part III, Tract I, Book III, Chapter VIII,”
in A Letter to the Friars Minor and Other Writings, Arthur Stephen McGrade and
John Kilcullen, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 210; “A matter of
faith is not always defined by the arbitrary will of the Roman pontiff alone
for he could be a heretic . . . . Indeed in decisions on matters of faith which
is why he possesses the primacy, he is subject to the council of the Catholic
Church,” Nicholas of Cusa (1991 [1443]), The Catholic Concordance, Paul E
Sigmund, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): (I.61) 43.451 Yves-Marie
Berce (1996), The Birth of Absolutism: A History of France, 1598-1661 (New
York: St. Martin’s Press): 62.452 “If the earthly power errs, it shall be
judged by the spiritual power, if a lesser spiritual power errs it shall be
judged by its superior, but if the supreme spiritual power errs it can be
judged only by God not by man,” “Unam Sanctum” (1302), in Brian Tierney, ed.,
The Crisis of Church and State 1050-1300 (Medieval Academy Reprints for
Teaching 21) (Toronto: University of Toronto Press,1988): 189.
508 “God bestows on
kings lawfully constituted, whether by divine inspiration or permission [of]
the peoples this prerogative of authority, which is superior to all power of
the people,” William Barclay (1954 [1600]), The Kingdom and the Regal Power,
trans. George Albert Moore (Chevy Chase, MD: Country Dollar Press): 145.
509 Bodin’s Six Books
of the Republic “was arguably the most original and influential work of
political philosophy to be written in the sixteenth century,” Quentin Skinner
(1978), The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Volume I: The Renaissance
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press):208.
510 James B Collins
(2001), “Noble Political Ideology and the Estates General of Orleans and Pontoise: French Republicanism,” Historical Reflections
27(2): 219-40.
511 Richard Bonney
(1990), “Bodin and the Development of the French Monarchy,”Transactions
of the Royal Historical Society 40: 43-61.
512 Armand Jean du
Plessis, Duke of Richelieu (1968 [1638]), The Political Testament of Cardinal
Richelieu, Henry Bertram Hill, trans. (Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin
Press): 69.
513 Ibid., 71.
514 Ibid., 72.
515 Rivalries between
Protestants and Catholics for positions in the Habsburg court, a rivalry that
more often than not swung in favor of the Catholics, produced political
divisions that mirrored the religious divisions in the Empire. Historian Karin
J MacHardy calls this process “confessionalizing
patronage,” further demonstrating the inextricability of religion and politics
in the early seventeenth century, War, Religion, and Court Patronage in
Habsburg Austria: The Social and Cultural Dimensions of Political Interaction,
1521-1622 (New York: Palgrave MacMillen): 198.
516 Robert Bireley
(2003), The Jesuits and the Thirty Years War: Kings, Courts, and Confessors
(New York: Cambridge University Press).
517 German Catholic
princes were in a precarious position. The Emperor was able to demand more
authority from the princes to counter the Protestant threat. However, although
the Catholic princes benefited from the weakening of Protestantism, they also
found themselves less able to counter the Emperor. A similar process had
occurred in France as the struggle against the Huguenots had provided Richelieu
was the opportunity to centralize authority in the hands of the king. It may be
true in general that the Reformation (specifically the entrance of a new source
of transcendent credibility into the European system) was a more significant
factor in the decline of the power of the nobility than war or other
hypothesized factors.
518 Paul Douglas
Lockhart (1995), “Religion and Princely Liberties: Denmark’s Intervention in
the Thirty Years War, 1618-1625,” International History Review 17(1): 1-22.
519 RJ Knecht (1991),
Richelieu: Profiles in Power (Harlow, England: Longman): 169-189. Richelieu
founded the Academie Francaise in 1634, which was designed “to harness artists
and writers to the chariot of the state, to present a favorable image of the
king and his government,” Peter Burke (1992), The Fabrication of Louis XIV (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press): 185. Richelieu also established a weekly
newspaper, the Gazette, that supported government policies, Howard M Solomon
(1972), Public Welfare, Science and Propaganda in Seventeenth-Century France
(Princeton: Princeton University Press): 111. Richelieu demonstrated a deep
interest in using the arts (e.g., paintings, statuary) to portray the king (and
himself) in favorable ways. One example of this use of the arts is the
establishment of a ballet company, which became an important tool to generate
nationalist sentiment and mock France’s many enemies; Marie-Claude Canova-Green
(1995), “Dance and Ritual: The Ballet des nations at the Court of Louis XIII,”
Renaissance Studies 9(4): 395-403.
520 Michael Roberts
(1973), Gustavus Adolphus and the Rise of Sweden (London: English Universities
Press).
521 Richard Bonney
(1976), “The Secret Expenses of Richelieu and Mazarin,” English Historical
Review 91(361): 825-36.
522 Toby Osborne
(2002), Dynasty and Diplomacy in the Court of Savoy: Political Culture and the
Thirty Years’ War (Cambridge Studies in Italian History and Culture Series) (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press).
523 Ibid., 140.
524 David Parrott
(2001), Richelieu’s Army: War, Government, and Society in France, 1624-1642
(New York: Cambridge University Press).
525 Justifications
for war continued for a while to revolve around defending Protestantism.
Recognizing that alliance with Catholic France toward that end would quickly
undermine the justification, Swedish leaders began to change their
justifications, Partel Piirimae
(2002), “Just War in Theory and Practice: The Legitimation of Swedish
Intervention in the Thirty Years War,” Historical Journal 45(3): 499-523.
526 Gary Nichols
(1989), “The Economic Impact of the Thirty Years’ War in Habsburg Austria,”
East European Quarterly 23(3): 257-68. Nichols argues that economic factors,
not religious ones, convinced persons in the Habsburg Empire to unite behind
the Emperor to end the war. However, I would argue economic factors could only
have an impact after the introduction of proto-nationalism had weakened the
religious factors that had dominated at the start of the war. This explanation
is also supported by Nichols data.
527 RA Stradling
(1986), “Olivares and the Origins of the Franco-Spanish War, 1627-1636,”
English Historical Review 100(398): 68-94.
528 Richard Bonney
(1991), The European Dynastic States, 1494-1660 (Oxford: Oxford University
Press): 198.
529 Piirimae (2002).
530 Steve Murdoch,
ed. (2001), Scotland and the Thirty Years War, 1618-1648 (History of Warfare
6), (Leiden: Brill).
531 Bireley, The
Jesuits and the Thirty Years War: 167-203.
532 Ibid., 160-64.
533 The Westphalian
settlement recognized this new, albeit tenuous, alliance. Institutionally, the
Imperial Diet adopted new rules that said matters that came before it must
receive a joint resolution of Catholics (Corpus Catholicorum)
and all Protestants (Corpus Evangelicorum), Richard
Bonney (2002), The Thirty Years’ War, 1618-1648 (Oxford: Osprey Publishing):
88-89. A Protestant alliance was possible now largely because proto-nationalism
made the crucial differences between the Lutherans and Calvinists less
significant.
534 Ronald G Asch
(2000), “Religious Toleration, the Peace of Westphalia and the German
Territorial Estates,” Parliaments, Estates & Representation 20: 75-89.
535 John RD Coffey
(2000), Persecution and Toleration in Protestant England, 1558-1689 (Longman).
536 Quoted in Bonney
(1991), European Dynastic States: 201.
537 MS Anderson
(1998), War and Society in Europe of the Old Regime, 1618-1789
(Gloucestershire: Sutton Publishing): 82-94.
538 Bonney (1991),
European Dynastic States: 423.
539 Stephane Beaulac
(2004), The Word Sovereignty in Bodin and Vattel and the Myth of Westphalia
(Developments in International Law 21) (Boston: Martinus Nijhoff
Publishers): 40, 97.
540 Ronald G Asch
(1997), The Holy Roman Empire and Europe, 1618-1648 (New York: St. Martin’s
Press); Andreas Osiander (1994), The States System of Europe, 1640-1990
(Oxford: Clarendon Press); Stephen Krasner (1993), “Westphalia and All That,”
in Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change,
Judith Goldstein and Robert O Keohane, eds. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press).
541 Daniel Philpott
(2001), Revolutions in Sovereignty: How Ideas Shaped Modern International
Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press): 136.
For updates click homepage here