By
Eric Vandenbroeck and co-workers
The U.S., U.K.,
Australia and India each fall under the umbrella of the common law family,
although the legal tradition of each maintains unique aspects. Each of these
four states has also been active in the past several decades in participating
in UN actions and sending its troops to various areas, whether as part of a
peace-keeping team or as another type of force.1 Moreover, each of these states
has been engaged in armed conflict with another state in the last half century.
This means that each of these four states has had to consider the issue of
whether their personnel could be accused of a crime and brought before the ICC.
These similarities provide for a common background from which to examine the
interpretations made by the four states, and given their similarities in
historical legal development and current contemporary actions, isolating the effect
of the various attributes of legal tradition should be possible.
The legal traditions
of both the United States and Australia have been discussed in part three and four,
respectively.
Universal Jurisdiction
Universal
jurisdiction provides entities (in this case the ICC) with the authority to try
persons for crimes, whether or not the person is a national of a particular
state or the crime was committed in or against a particular state or its
citizens. Universal jurisdiction is applicable to those crimes which are
considered an affront to the international community as a whole, such as
genocide, war crimes, and crimes against humanity. While long recognized in
international law, particularly in relation to states’ right to combat piracy,
the current conception of universal jurisdiction has only been considered an
international legal principle since the Nuremburg trials at the end of WWII.2
It has been re-codified in each of the treaties establishing the international
criminal tribunals and special tribunals over the past several decades and is
the core component of the International Criminal Court.
Historically, the
idea of a universal principle of jurisdiction was limited to states’ ability to
prosecute pirates, whatever their nationality happened to be3. More modern
understandings of this legal principle attach primarily to human rights
violations4; those crimes that are so universally condemned that any nation in
the world has the authority to exercise jurisdiction over suspects and
perpetrators, without the consent of that individual’s state of nationality.5
As with the other legal principles examined in part 3 and 4 , the United States
played a key role in the development of universal jurisdiction, serving as a
leading proponent of the Nuremburg trials, as well as the Security Council
resolutions authorizing the international criminal tribunals for Rwanda and the
former Yugoslavia. The U.S. has even recognized the veracity of this principle
within its domestic law, with both the Second Circuit Court of Appeals and the
Sixth Circuit Court of Appeals identifying human rights violations as acceptable
bases for a state to maintain universal jurisdiction over an individual when
neither the persons involved, nor the crime itself, have any direct relation to
the state6. Rather the jurisdiction stems from the harm to all mankind, as well
as international peace and security.
Currently, the
concept of universal jurisdiction has been expanded somewhat, largely through
the efforts of individual states. The desire has been to allow for the
prosecution of any individual accused of committing any crime which offends the
sense of global humanity. Some of the best known recent examples of this
expansion include the British High Court’s decision to allow the extradition of
Augusto Pinochet to Spain to stand trial for actions committed while he was
head of Chile, and Belgium’s 1993 law which allows Belgium to prosecute persons
for genocide, war crimes, and crimes against humanity on the basis of universal
jurisdiction in absentia.7
Specifically in the
context of the International Criminal Court, the concept of universal
jurisdiction provides for prosecution of individuals accused of crimes of
genocide, war crimes, and crimes against humanity committed after July 1, 2002,
the date the Rome Statute entered into effect.8 One caveat, however, is that
the crimes committed must of such a grave nature as to rise to the level of
crimes which are of concern to the international community as a whole.9 It is
this conception of universal jurisdiction which states evaluated when
determining their position on the ICC.
Traditional theories
of international relations focused on power and interests would hypothesize
that no state would accede to the Rome Statute of the International Criminal
Court unless it would improve its power position within the international
community by doing so, or in some other way improve or protect its interests.
Given the obligations undertaken by a state party to the ICC, and the
relinquishment of a certain sense of sovereignty to become a party, it is
likely these theories would posit no state would sign on to the ICC statute
unless the most powerful states also agreed to do so.
Upon closer
examination, however, these traditional theories fall short of being able to
explain state participation in the ICC.10 For example, for the realists, an
international legal institution such as the ICC is unlikely to be created in
the first place because it is
contrary to the fundamental notions of state sovereignty, and the freedom of
states to act as they see fit to protect their interests. Yet created it was;
and even though they all did not ultimately sign on, most members of the United
Nations participated in the sessions drafting the Rome Statute.
Moreover, realist
theory would contend that if an international criminal court was Created, it
would only be created by powerful states to further their own purposes. Yet, in
the case of the ICC, many of the most powerful states – the United States, China,
India, and Russia among them – are all opposed to the Rome State. Despite this
opposition by the powerful states, however, the Rome Statute entered into force
and presently has 139 parties, even though none of the four states listed above
has changed its mind. Neo-liberal institutionalist theory as well faces some
problems in adequately trying to explain state acceptance of the Rome Statute.
According to Wippman:
[A] neo-liberal
institutionalist analysis, which sees states as rational actors in pursuit of
efficient means to realize individual and collective interests, captures only
part of what transpired at Rome. To some extent, the Rome treaty was motivated
by a desire to solve collective action problems and to reduce the transaction
costs inherent in establishing ad hoc tribunals. But the Rome treaty was driven
even more fundamentally by a desire on the part of many participants in the
negotiations to develop and stabilize norms of legitimate behavior by states
and non-state actors. … [R]ationalist analysis works
best in areas where states can plausibly be seen to have clear, pre-existing
material interests; it does not work well in explaining the creation of
international organizations such as the ICC that are driven in significant part
by normative as well as material impulses.11
Because the primary
function of the ICC is normative in its foundations, the organization does not
function they way institutionalists might argue it should in order to garner
the support of states.
The incongruency of
the establishment and entry into force of the Rome Statue of the International
Criminal Court with traditional international relations theory calls therefore
for new explanations for state behavior. Given the normative component of the
ICC, and the fact that it does require relinquishment of sovereignty as well as
put normative constraints on state behavior in terms of what is the appropriate
course of action, an explanation devoted to understanding the cultural and
normative reasons behind state action – such as that concerning legal tradition
– is necessary. In particular such an explanation “requires consideration of
how actors’ interests and identities interacted to produce positions on
particular contested issues.”12
Two forthcoming works
which do consider legal tradition address some of these concerns. In her
forthcoming work on human, Beth Simmons examines the differences between common
law states and civil law states in their adherence to international human rights
treaties.13 She suggests that, due to variation between the common and civil
law, civil law countries are more likely than their common law counterparts to
commit to international human rights treaties. While Professor Simmons includes
components of legal tradition in her analysis, focusing in particular on the
fact that the use of precedent and the power of the judiciary present in the
common law systems is absent in the civil law system. However, in the her final
analysis she retains the common law/civil law division, grouping states
generally in one of two categories. While this may provide initial evidence as
to the differing behavior of the two types of legal traditions, I suggest that
this will not fully explain state behavior. Within the civil law tradition,
there are state from Europe, Africa, Asia, and South America, each of which
adhere to the general tenets of civil law outlined by Simmons – adherence to a
code-style of law and the integration of the judiciary within the government –
but which are significantly different in the overall attributes of their legal
traditions, and which behave very different in terms of international law. The
same, this chapter seeks to demonstrate is true for the common law nations,
even though there are many fewer of them.
A second piece by
Sara McLaughlin Mitchell and Emilia Powell, forthcoming in the Journal of
Politics, also makes an argument incorporating legal tradition. Mitchell and
Powell examine state acceptance of the jurisdiction of the International Court
of Justice and seek to understand the characteristics which make a state likely
to accept the absolute jurisdiction of the ICJ versus an acceptance of
jurisdiction with reservations.
Mitchell and Powell
look at three different legal traditions – the common law, the civil law, and
Islamic law – but like Simmons, lump state’s under these general headings
without delving into the differences among them. As stated in the previous
paragraph, we suggest that this general categorization does indeed improve on
earlier work which does not consider legal tradition at all, but it still
leaves much room for improvement because it fails to explain the frequent
differences which occur within the general legal families.
(A) United States
As discussed in
chapter four, the legal tradition of the United States is very closely tied to
the revolutionary ideals which prompted the creation of the United States
Constitution, and country’s subsequent political and legal structure. This
includes a foundational institutionalization of the separation of powers and a
significant role for the judiciary, as well as subsequent actions including the
creation of a Bill of Rights and the focus on an entrepreneurial spirit. These
influences have resulted in the U.S. legal tradition possessing the following
attributes: a purpose of law focused on the individual; the primary
responsibility for the creation and amendment of law found in the judicial
branch; a dualist approach to international law; and a hierarchy of sources of
law which places the U.S. Constitution as the apex, and the decisions of the
judiciary – as the final arbiters of the Constitution – second.
As described in P. 3
of this investigation, these attributes of the U.S. legal tradition hinder the
relationship between domestic law and international law within the U.S.
tradition. Given the focus on individual rights and freedoms and the underlying
belief that law should be used as a mechanism by which to punish actions which
have infringed on individual liberties, not to prevent individuals from acting
in the first place, the idea that international law could affect these
protections is one that is an anathema to the understanding of the role of law
in the United States. Again, this is not to say the United States does not
respect the rule of law, including the rule of international law, because
indeed it does. The United States, as demonstrated, is often a leader in terms
of pushing for new concepts of international law, offering expanded
protections. Moreover, the U.S. couches much of its diplomacy in the language
of international law, and always has. The issue is not with the U.S. belief in
the value of international law over the broad course of the country’s history.
The issue is that due to the way the U.S. legal tradition has developed over
the past 250 years, there is an extreme reluctance to accept any outside
interference with the foundational legal principles of the state, as well as a
penchant to view international law as being as changeable and immutable as the
law of the United States.
(B) Australia
Australia, like the
United States, has the historical origins of its legal tradition in the common
law of England. As described in chapter five, however, the development of the
legal tradition from these origins has been influenced by different factors and
taken a slightly different track in Australia than in the United States. With a
much longer period as a British colony, with its history as a penal colony run
by an authoritarian governor, and with independence not grounded in a
revolutionary movement, but rather stemming from an Act of the British
Parliament, the foundations of Australia’s tradition do not maintain the same
sacred aura as that of the United States. Moreover, whereas the Australian
tradition does share similarities to that of the U.S. in terms of the respect
for individual freedoms and entrepreneurship, the translation of these freedoms
into a sacred respect for individual rights enshrined in a constitution, does
not exist in Australia.
This history has led
to the development of the following attributes in the Australian legal tradition:
a focus on the individual in terms of the purpose of the law, but a focus
centered on individual freedoms along, rather than individual rights and
freedoms as in the U.S.; a system of judge-made law, but also a system in which
more power is left to the states vis-a-vis the federal government; a dualist
approach to international law; and, a hierarchy of sources centered on judicial
decision and parliamentary statute. The Australian Constitution plays a much
less significant role in the Australian legal system than does the U.S.,
largely due to the absence of a Bill of Rights. As with the U.S., these
attributes can hinder the relationship between international law and domestic
law within the Australian legal system. This, in turn, can influence the method
of interpretation a state adopts towards a principle of international law. In
the Australian case, there also appears to be a general reluctance to too
completely accept the binding effect of international law, largely due to the
country’s colonial history and its independent nature.
(C) United Kingdom
As discussed before
in this investigation, the origins of the common law tradition come from
England. It was in England in 1066, that William the Conqueror planted the
seeds for the common law system by centralizing judicial authority at
Westminster14. In order to reign in the chaos that numerous local systems of
law can have on a unified legal system, the first judges began collecting the
laws common to the majority of the people and applying those uniformly to all
court cases15. It is from this – the identification and application of the law
common to all – that we get the name for the common law tradition. From this
starting point, many of the attributes most closely associated with the common
law tradition developed, including: the supremacy of judicial decision as the
primary source of law and as the source of the creation and amendment of law
beyond the sovereign16, the focus on the individual case, as opposed to the
communal well-being, through the disposition of judicial proceedings; and the
separation between domestic law and foreign affairs17.
Despite these common
origins, however, as is evident from the cases of the United States and
Australia described above, subsequent developments in each state’s legal
tradition have resulted in slightly different attributed among the four states
– even though they all have the same foundations. In England this legal
development included three primary factors which have had a subsequent
influence on what today is the legal tradition of the United Kingdom. The first
of these is the emergence of Parliament as the primary force for creating and
amending law in the U.K. No longer are the courts responsible for this task. In
fact, in a complete opposite trajectory of development from that of the United
States (where courts have steadily gained power over the years), the courts in
the U.K. have steadily lost power. This is due to a number of factors,
including reactions to the authoritarianism of the monarchy and the desire to
have the government better represent the people18; the creation of the United
Kingdom, which joined together the common law system of England, with the Roman
law system of Scotland, and the customary legal system of Wales; and, the lack
of a written constitution in England to dictate the separation of powers and
the authority of the Court. Not only does this latter omission mean that no
constitutional power is specifically dictated to the judicial branch, but it
also means there is no document upon which the justices can base an attempt to
gain more power (as the Marshall Court did in Marbury v. Madison)19.
The second factor
which has pushed England in a different direction than its common law heirs,
is, as mentioned in the previous paragraph, the lack of a written constitution
and the impact that has on all manner of political and legal structures. Much
of what gives the United States its unique legal tradition is the foundational
nature of the U.S. Constitution, and the close relationship between the fight
for independence in the U.S. and how people understand the Constitution as a
continuation of those ideals20. The United Kingdom, on the contrary, lacks both
a similarly significant foundational moment in terms of its own perceptions of
itself, as well as any core written text outlining the institutions of the
country. The “constitution” of the United Kingdom is rather composed of a
series of documents that span both time and type of law21, and includes the
Magna Carta (1215)22, the Petition of Right (1628), the Bill of Rights Act
(1689) 23, the Act of Union with Scotland (1707), the European Communities Act (1972)24,
and the Human Rights Act (1998). Coupled with this, the institutions of the
U.K. have developed over time, and in a relatively non-confrontational manner.
Much of this, we suggest, is due to the continuous overarching presence of the
monarchy which, even when it itself was the object of complaint, maintained a
certain institutional structure within the state. This has resulted in an
interrelated set of institutions that have developed over time, not by the
dictates of a foundational legal document such as a constitution, but rather by
the practicalities of the changing nature of society as a whole. This creates
very different perceptions of law in the U.K. than in the U.S. or Australia25.
The third influence
that has shaped the legal tradition of the U.K. over the past 50 years, and is
the dominant force responsible for the shift in the U.K.’s interpretation of
international law, is the U.K.’s membership in the European Union. Up to the point
of World War II, the attributes of the British legal tradition fairly closely
mirrored those of the United States, save for the decreased power of the U.K.
courts compared to their American brethren. Both states largely focused on the
individual in terms of the purpose of their laws, and the judiciary played a
significant role in each states legal system.
Moreover, both the
U.K. and U.S. were largely dualist in their approach to international law,
preferring to ‘go it alone’ or work in a specific, negotiated international
framework rather than under the rubric of binding international law. With the
end of the war, however, and the realization by the European states that
preventing another war on the continent had to be a top priority resulted
ultimately in the creation of the European Coal and Steel Community, which
ultimately morphed into the European Union, a regional organization with its
own legal personality, to which member states surrender of good deal of
sovereignty. Upon becoming a member of the EU in 1973, the United Kingdom
became subject to the same limits on its sovereignty. Moreover, as the EU
continued to grow, expanding its authority over areas such as human rights and
social issues, the attributes of the British legal system began to change to
fulfil its obligations as a member of the EU. These changes resulted in
somewhat different attributes of the British legal tradition today than were
seen prior to the 20th century.
(1) Purpose of Law
Due to the historical
importance of conflict being solved through the court system, the purpose of
law in the United Kingdom is largely still viewed as one which provides
protections for individuals in making their claims26. However, this focus on
the individual, rather than creating a strong sense of law promoting what is
best for the community, has been eroded somewhat over the past century, both by
an emerging socialist trend “attempting to create a new social order”27, and by
the U.K.’s membership in the European Union. The EU, given its focus as a
regional organization, is communal in nature. The entire idea behind the
European Union was that the creation of closer cooperation between European
states would lessen the likelihood of states engaging in conflict with each
other over their individual interests. Rather, closer cooperation would cause
states to think of what is best for the community. This has become reflected to
some extent in the British legal tradition. For example, the U.K. has signed on
to the European Convention on Human Rights and has accepted both European Court
of Human Rights and European Court of Justice jurisdiction over the disposition
of cases. This treaty, as well as the workings of these courts, focus on the
communal purpose of law rather than the individual.
There has not been a
complete shift in the view by the British of the purpose of law. The U.K. still
retains sovereignty over certain areas, such as a number of social issues,
rather than relinquish sovereignty to the EU. The U.K. also maintains its independence
in terms of monetary policy, immigration policy, and national security and
defense. In these areas, the U.K. is still reluctant to accept outside
interference with its sovereignty as an individual state. In the same way, the
purpose of law in the United Kingdom is still viewed in many areas as
protecting the rights of the individual, rather than fostering the good of
community28. Outside interference with individual freedom of action is still
often frowned upon, but is viewed with less suspicion that, for example, in the
United States.
(2) Legal Institutions
The British
institutional structure is much more similar to that of Australia than it is to
the United States. Britain maintains a parliamentary system with a monarch as
the head of state and a prime minister as the head of government. Without a
written constitution, the relationships between the branches of government have
developed by custom over time. While a democracy with a modern government, the
concepts of separation of powers and checks and balances that dominate the
perception of institutional structure in the United States do not exist29. This
is most evident in the interrelationship between the executive and legislative
branches in which the Prime Minister, the principle member of the executive
branch, survives only at the favor of Parliament30. The interrelationship does
not end there, however, for the House of Lords, the highest judicial body in
the United Kingdom, is also composed of members of the upper house of
Parliament. Despite this, however, the judiciary in the United Kingdom does retain
its independence from the other branches of government, although it does not
hold the power of checks and balances the U.S. Supreme Court does.
Moreover, within the
English tradition it has become the purview of parliament to create and amend
the laws, not the judiciary. While historically it was the judiciary which was
responsible for such actions, this changed in the 18th and early 19th centuries
when the people revolted over the dominance held by the monarchy and upper
classes over all branches of government31. As in France, the judiciary were
seen as being a part of the upper class and under the influence of the
monarch.32 In the latter half of the 19th century these beliefs came to be
codified in the perceptions of “almost all politicians, lawyers, and political
theorists … that Parliament possessed a legally unlimited legislative authority
within Britain” and by 1871 it was held that the courts had no authority “to
act as regents over what is done by parliament.”33 These laws gave the
preponderance of power to the parliament, as representatives of the people, as
opposed to the courts overseen by the aristocracy. This set-up remains to this day.
Today, the legal system in the U.K. is such that parliament is the only
institution which can make and amend laws. This notion of parliamentary
sovereignty is “central to English constitutionalism”.34 The courts are
responsible for interpreting the law, but may not judge an act of parliament
invalid35. This gives a preponderance of the power over legal enactment and
amendment to the parliament, which is an attribute more closely aligned with
civil law traditions like that of France, than common law traditions like that
of the United States.
While the creation
and amendment of law may differ in the United Kingdom, however, the U.K.’s
approach to international law remains largely similar to that of both the U.S.
and Australia in that it is generally dualist in nature.36 As stated by Rosalyn
Higgins and quoted in chapter five, the common law countries adhere “resolutely
to the dualist approach.”37. However, as mentioned above, the absolute nature
of this approach has shifted slightly in the United Kingdom as a result of the
country’s membership in the European Union. EU membership automatically
requires states to relinquish a modicum amount of sovereignty to an
international organization. Moreover, EU membership dictates that member states
are responsible for implementing EU regulations into their domestic legal
systems. For all EU members, therefore, this has required domestic legal
changes authorizing a monist approach to EU legislation. Therefore, the U.K.
has become essentially monist in their approach in any areas over which the EU
has primary control. However, in those areas in which the U.K. retains national
sovereign control, the state remains true to its dualist origins.
(2) Sources of Law
The U.K. differs from
the United States in that it has neither a written constitution to serve as the
foundational source of law38, nor do judges have the power of judicial
review39. As explained in the case of the U.S. in part four, the principle
reason the judiciary remain the primary source of law in the United States –
even though the amount of statutory law has increased dramatically – is that it
is the judiciary which is responsible for the ultimate determination of the
meaning of both the U.S. Constitution and any federal law passed by Congress.
Because the U.S. retains the power of judicial review, this gives the U.S.
judicial branch enormous power and authority. This is not the case in the
United Kingdom. While the British judicial branch retains the power of
precedent, it does not maintain ultimate authority over the interpretation of
law; that right belongs to parliament40. While legislation has traditionally
“occupied only a secondary position in English law and was limited to
correcting or complementing the work accomplished by judicial decision”, today
the relative position of the two sources of law is largely reversed41.
Therefore, parliamentary enactments are the primary source of law in the U.K.,
rather than judicial decisions.42
Given the historical
importance of judicial decisions for the development of the British legal
tradition, however, judicial decision and case law still holds a pride of place
in the conceptions of many British citizens when it comes to sources of law43.
Therefore, even
though the power of the judiciary in England may not be what it once was, case
law is still seen as the primary foundation of the U.K.’s legal tradition44.
This has an important implication for the influence that legal tradition may
have on a state’s interpretation of international law. As discussed in chapter
four in relation to the United States, a belief in law as primarily a
judge-made entity creates a different perspective about the changing nature of
law. By its very nature, a legal system based on judicial decision is a
bottom-up system, where individual cases come before the court and changes in
the law come with new facts in the case. It is a system in which actions happen
first and judicial approval or disavowal of those acts happen second. Moreover,
while judges may not have the ability in the U.K. to review the
constitutionality of parliamentary action, they do maintain authority over
interpretation of the law, which can give them considerable power in
determining how law actually applies to the community.45 This creates a much
more flexible legal system, one which accepts a more malleable nature to the
law. This can then translate to international law as well.
The U.K. does retain,
however, the historical common law aversion to doctrinal writings being
considered as sources of law46. The laws of the U.K. are not laws of the
universities47. Given the historical important of the judiciary in the
development of the British legal tradition, it was the judges who were
considered the legal experts, not scholars48. Therefore, as in the U.S. and
Australia, scholarly writings have never taken on the importance they have in
other countries such as France and Germany where judges were not long-schooled
legal specialists and doctrinal writings provided valuable guidance on the law.
(D) India
India, today, is
considered part of the common law family. The history of India’s legal
tradition, however, is significantly different from that of either the United
States or Australia. For one thing, with over one billion people, India has a
larger population to govern than any country in the world except China.
Moreover, among these one billion are at least seven different major religious
groups, eighteen different official languages, and at least three major ethnic
groups49, not to mention residual beliefs in the caste system by elements of
the population.50 The influences which have shaped the development of the
Indian legal tradition are more varied than in the Anglo-Saxon states.
These include the Hindu
legal tradition, Islamic law tradition, and tribal or customary law. Moreover,
despite the modernity of India’s existing legal system, these ancient,
religious and tribal influences remain to some extent within the rule of law.
These differences notwithstanding, however, since Indian independence in 1950
India has been considered part of the common law family of states51. The
underlying structure of India’s legal system, as well as the general operation
of the rule of law in contemporary times, does place India in the company of
the other states discussed in this chapter52. India, therefore, provides an
interesting comparison to the U.K., U.S., and Australia as a modern common law
country, with ancient roots.
The three major
influences on the development of the Indian legal tradition are Hinduism,
Islam, and the British colonial presence. Each of these has its own individual
legal tradition, and the mixing of the three has shaped the nature of the India
tradition. Hinduism is the oldest influence on the Indian legal tradition, and
indeed, even today forms part of the core of the Indian legal system. The laws
of Hindu India can be traced as far back as 2500 BC. The Hindu tradition is
based on Dharma, which is the belief “that there exists a universal order
inherent in the nature of things, necessary for the preservation of the world,
and of which the gods themselves are merely the custodians.”53
Like the Shari’a in the Islamic legal tradition, Dharma in the Hindu
tradition encompasses the “whole of man’s behavior” and does not distinguish
between religious duties and legal obligations.54 Any concept of individual
rights is foreign to the Hindu tradition which, like the Islamic religious
tradition, focuses on maintaining balance and harmony within the community, and
the principles that each person must follow if they wish to be a good person
and reach the desired place in the afterworld55.
One belief that
distinguishes the Hindu tradition from that of the other religious legal
traditions, however, is that within the tradition the duties and obligations
each individual must carry out to be a good person and achieve their desired
place in the afterworld, varies according to each person’s status.56 The Hindu
tradition divides people into four primary social groups, each with its own
rules and obligations57. This division is necessary in the Hindu tradition to
ensure the proper balance within nature. This division is also the origin of
the Indian caste system, which has had a significant influence on the
development of the legal tradition of India, and continues to play a role in
the legal system of modern India, despite the abolishment of the caste system
in the Indian Constitution.
In the historical
Hindu legal system, rules were primarily enacted, implemented, and enforced at
the local community level58. The village panchayat was largely responsible for
hearing and deciding legal disputes on the basis of religious laws and existing
local custom59. Given the diversity which existed throughout the Indian
subcontinent60, there could be a significant difference between the laws as
applied in the local communities.
In the 16th century,
the Mongols invaded India and brought with them elements of the Islamic law
tradition61. While similar to the Hindu tradition in terms of general structure
– for example, in that laws could only be created by the gods and law covered
both religious and secular behavior – Islamic law is much more rigid in its
tenets than the Hindu tradition. Perhaps recognizing these differences, the
Islamic rulers did not impose Shari’a on the Hindu
population in the territories of India they commanded, but rather allowed
Hindus and Muslims to retain their separate traditions and rules of law62. Thus
a dual legal system sprang up in which Islamic law and courts applied for
Muslims and Hindu law and courts applied to Hindus. Into this situation of dual
legal traditions arrived the British. Britain first gained a toehold in the
India sub-continent through the East India trading company in the 17th
century63. After the decline of Dutch and Spanish naval power, however, India
came fully under the authority of the United Kingdom. As was often the case
with their colonies, the U.K. did not impose British law on the Indian
population at the expense of their traditional legal system64. Rather, both the
Hindu and Muslim populations were able to continue to apply their own laws at
the local level. British law applied, in theory, only to British citizens and
in those circumstances where there was no local law or in which local law
offended the British sense of justice65.
Practically, however,
the British presence in India had a profound influence on the development of
the India legal tradition, both in terms of the recognition of Hindu law and in
terms of the growth and development of that law. As to the former, the recognition
by the British of both Hindu and Islamic law as equally valid legal systems,
moved Hindu law out of the shadows from which it operated while India was under
Mongol control.66 At the same time, however, despite the best efforts of
British judges to apply traditional law to cases between Hindus, the absence of
authoritative English translations of Hindu laws coupled with over-reliance on
Hindu “legal specialists” led to a distortion of the traditional Hindu law67.
The results of this, as well, were both positive and negative. Positive in that
the centralized nature of the British system allowed for the unification and
clarification of the extremely diverse legal rules which were found throughout
India68. This ultimately led to the creation of a national legal system69.
Negative in that the
historical extent to which Hindu law applied to govern all situations in the
lives of Hindus was dramatically reduced. Under the British rule, Hindu law
(and Muslim law as well) came to apply solely to those cases involving personal
status, such as marriage, birth, and death70.
The legal tradition
of India today has retained elements of each of these three primary influences.
While the majority of legal institutions are based on the British (or other
common law) system(s), at the local level, the use of religious laws still exists,
and is in fact recognized as valid by the federal law.
(1) Purpose of Law
The purpose of law in
India is centered on the community, rather than the individual. This draws both
on the historical religious influences on the legal tradition, as well as the
modern goals of the state’s post-independence legal system. As described in
part four in relation to Islamic law, religious legal traditions, by their very
nature, focus on a communal purpose of law. The goals of such legal traditions
are to ensure the well-being of the community as a whole, and that everyone is
able to achieve the best life possible in this world to attain the rewards of
the next. The Hindu tradition reflects that notion as well, focusing on the
harmony of the community and the balance of man and nature.
Modern developments
of the Indian tradition have furthered this focus of law on the community, as
opposed to the individual. First, resulting from the nationalist pride that
developed during the movement to gain independence from Britain, and later
stemming from the Indian government’s desire to protect the good of all members
of Indian society71. First, the development of Indian nationalism, as was the
case in Turkey and Egypt described in chapter four, created a greater awareness
of the need for a unified, continually-developed Indian community72. Given the
widespread divergence in economic and social status within the country, only
through a concentrated effort of protecting all members of Indian society was
it perceived possible for India to develop.
Second, despite the
abolition of the caste system in the Indian Constitution, there was still a
great deal of discrimination against those perceived to be of the lower
classes. One of the early goals of the post-independence Indian legal system
was to ensure the equality of everyone, even if that meant favoring the lower
classes at the expense of the privileged73.
This is reflected in
constitutional rules, not only abolishing untouchability, but allowing the
reservation of a certain number of seats for former untouchables in educational
institutions and places of public employment.74
This concept of a
communal purpose of law is further reflected in the Indian Constitution, which
defines the nation in the Preamble as a “sovereign socialist democratic
republic”.75 The Constitution also focuses on creating a unified society by
prohibiting discrimination based on social class. This is an effort to undo
thousands of years of history in which, as described above, Indian society was
divided by religious belief, into social classes, each of which was believed to
have its own place in Hindu society. Article 15 of the Indian Constitution
prohibits any form of discrimination based on caste.76 Moreover, the Indian
Constitution does not uphold ideas of equal protection in the same manner as
the United States, recognizing instead that “certain castes, tribes or
economically weak social groups should possess a special status.”77
Furthermore, the
governmental institutions of India are all guided by a separate series of
fundamental principles outlined in Part 4 of the Constitution, which call upon
them to frame every policy, piece of legislation, and judicial decision in such
a way as to establish and maintain a new social order in which justice –
whether social, economic, and political – shall inform all the institutions of
national life.78 These principles include such community-oriented tenets as
ensuring that ownership and control of the material resources of the community
are distributed to best achieve the common good, and the assurance that the
operation of the economic system does not lead to the concentration of wealth
and the means of production in the hands of the few to the detriment of the
common good.79
(2) Legal Institutions
The legal
institutional structure of India is a cross between that of the U.K., the US,
Ireland, and Australia. The drafters of the Indian Constitution drew from the
legal and political structures of all four of these common law countries when
they were setting up their postindependence system. Today, Indian maintains a
mixed presidential parliamentary system with the addition of a relatively
powerful President as well as a Prime Minister appointed by the President from
the legislative body.80 The preponderance of the authority lies with the lower
house of parliament, the 552-member Lok Sabha, which has the authority to enact
legislation, as well as dismantle the government through a vote of no
confidence.81 India does maintain an independent judiciary, and the judicial
branch possesses a level of power that is a cross between that of the U.K. and
that of the U.S. For example, while the Supreme Court of India does possess the
power of judicial review of legislation for conformance with the principles of
the Constitution, the ease with which Parliament can amend the Constitution
makes this a much less powerful tool in India than in the United States82.
However, given the view of the Indian population that the Supreme Court is the
most uncorrupt branch of the government and one of the most respected83,
politically it can be damaging for Parliament to amend the Constitution to
thwart a Supreme Court ruling.
The institution
primarily responsible for creating and amending law in India is the parliament.
As in England, the judicial branch is very active in creating a system of case
law based on the concepts of precedent and stare decisis84, but because there is
limited judicial review of the constitutionality of acts of the other branches
of government, the courts are without the primary power they possess in the
United States. The judiciary in India is consistently viewed by the Indian
public, however, as the most trustworthy of all of the government bodies, which
does give added weight to the authority of Indian judicial decisions as a
source of law (see below), but the judiciary is not primarily responsible for
making or amending law.
Following more
closely in the common law tradition, however, India maintains a clear dualist
position towards international law. With respect to international treaties to
which India becomes a party, separate action is required by parliament in order
for the treaty provisions to become binding law.
(2) Sources of Law
Historically, the
primary sources of law in India were the religious sastras and sustras, and the accepted interpretations of these works
(Vedas) by religious scholars. Legislation and judicial decisions were not held
to be sources of law under the Hindu tradition85. The prince was able to
legislate as necessary in order to order the community, but this legislation
was recognized only as a temporary need and was not able to conflict with or
supersede the tenets of Dharma86.
One important
criteria of the Hindu tradition, however, has always been its flexibility in
terms of the recognition of new laws. Unlike some other religious traditions,
in which change to the laws is very difficult to achieve, the Hindu tradition
accepts change as a natural part of life. The Dharma has “never purported to be
more than a body of ideal rules intended to guide men in their dealings.”87 Due
to its very nature, therefore, Dharma has always accepted that new laws will
have to be made by men to govern their current situations. Whether the laws are
created by custom, legislation, or judicial decision, the Hindu tradition has
always accepted manmade law as an essentially component of a functioning social
order, while at the same time recognizing the transient nature of this law and
the fact that it will continue to change and circumstances and societal needs
change88. This underlying attributed of the religious legal foundations of
Indian society has a profound influence on the perceptions of law held within
the country (and is indeed reflected in the malleable nature of the state’s own
constitution)89.
Today, the primary source
of law in India is the Constitution, followed by legislation90. India’s
Constitution entered into effect on January 26, 1950.91 While drawing on the
constitutional experiences of other common law countries, the Indian
Constitution is, however, very much unlike those of the other common law
countries in that, rather than serving as a relatively brief guide to
government structure and constitutionally-protected rights, it serves as a more
all-encompassing guide to government practice and individual behavior within
the state92. In fact, with its articles, is more akin to the Constitutions of
countries like Germany and Egypt, where the founding documents read more like
comprehensive codes than, for example, the U.S. Constitution93. The primary
objective of the Constitution is to ensure “social, economic, and political
justice to all citizens”.94
Because the Indian
Constitution is fairly easy to amend by parliament, and because the power of
judicial review of the Indian courts is minimal, judicial decisions do not
maintain the importance of place they possess in other common law countries.
The judiciary in modern India has, however, developed some authority on its own
as the most trusted branch of the Indian government.
Scholarly doctrine
may be considered a source of law in India, but largely within the realm of the
personal cases which may still be heard before religious-based tribunals. In
the same way, customary law still maintains a place in the Indian legal tradition,
but only through the local panchayat (meeting of the elders), which is able to
hear community and personal issues95.
One of the
overarching features of the modern Indian legal tradition, is the retention of
the influence of the ancient religious laws96. While practically speaking Hindu
or Islamic law is only applied by a few specific courts, in relatively few
cases, the influence of the religious traditions does continue to play a part
in the understanding of law within India. You see this reflected in the
continued understanding of the purpose of law as a communal endeavor. This
influence notwithstanding, however, the modern Indian legal tradition is one
closely related to its common law brethren, particularly in terms of
institutional structures such as the creation of law and approach to
international law. The latter attributes are sufficient for India to be
generally classified today as a member of the common law family. However, the
historical, religious attributes are enough to raise suspicions that India
might not approach international law in the same way as other common law
countries.
(E) Expectations
Given the fact that
each of the four countries examined has the origins of its modern tradition in
the English common law, many of the attributes of these countries are the
similar. In each of the four states the judiciary plays a greater role in the
creation and amendment of law than is seen in countries with foundations in the
civil law tradition. While none of the countries examined has a judiciary with
as extensive a power as that of the U.S. Supreme Court, judges do maintain a
special pride of place in the United Kingdom, Australia, and India. Moreover,
in each of the four states the use of the doctrinal writings of scholars as
authoritative sources of law is minimal in the creation, amendment, and
interpretation of law. Each of the four states, as well, generally adopts a
dualist position towards international law. Each of these attributes, as
described throughout the project, impedes the relationship between domestic and
international law.
This creates a sense
among policy-makers that international legal principles are not absolutely
binding in their existing form. This allows for the interpretation of
international law in new and different ways (although, again, as each of these
countries does generally adhere to the rule of law, including international
law, even new interpretations are firmly grounded in international legal
discourse).
Based on the general
categorization of these four states as members of the common law family, it
therefore could be expected that each of them would adopt a liberal
interpretation of international law: an interpretation grounded in the law, but
one which also allows for the consideration of state interests, changed
circumstances, and modern context. Indeed, this is the approach that is taken
by the existing work in the field which has dealt specifically with the
influence of legal tradition on state treatment of international law. These
studies have come to the conclusion that all common law countries, such as the
four examined here, would come to the same interpretation of international law.
To do so, however, would miss some of the very nuances that make the study of
legal tradition as an influential component of state policy-making a valuable
addition to the study of international law and international relations. The
very reason that such general classifications as common law and civil law do
not provide adequate explanations of state behavior is that each state
maintains slight differences in the underlying attributes which make up their
legal traditions and depending on the combination of these attributes the state
may or may not approach international law in the same way as other common law
states.
Based on more
traditional international relations theories focused on power and interests, it
would also likely be expected that each of these states would adopt a liberal
interpretation of international law, as it is the liberal interpretation which
gives a state the most freedom to consider its interests in formulation its
policies (again, none of these states will adopt an unrestricted interpretation
as they all adhere to the rule of law).
Given that each of
the four states has been active over the past decade in contributing troops to
United Nations missions, as well as regional missions, such as NATO in Bosnia;
and, given the fact the U.S., U.K., and Australia have been involved in conflicts
in Afghanistan and Iraq97, and India has been involved in continual skirmishes
with Pakistan98, there is a logical reason to expect each of the four to
approach the ICC in the same way. All four face also the potential that members
of their military or leadership will be indicted by the ICC. All four also face
the possibility of malicious or political cases being brought against their
citizens due to the unpopular nature of some of their actions. Based on these
similarities as well, under theories of power and interest it would also be
expected each of the states would interpret the international legal principle
of universal jurisdiction in the same way.
We believe however,
that these expectations are incorrect, and that, in fact, all four common law
states would not be expected to interpret the international law of universal
jurisdiction outlined in the Rome Statute of the ICC in the same way. The slight
variation among the states in terms of certain of their attributes, coupled
with the historical influences on the development of each countries legal
tradition, produces expectations that each of these four states might interpret
the international law of universal jurisdiction in a different way.
Table 1 summarizes
the attributes of the legal traditions of each of the four states examined
above. Both the United Kingdom and India have two columns. In the case of the
U.K., one identifies what the state’s attributes were before membership in the
European Union, and the corresponding expectation. The second identifies the
attributes and expectations since the U.K. became a member of the EU. For
purposes of India, the historical classification identifies attributes and
expectations prior to the imprint of the British tradition. The modern
classification highlights the attributes of the Indian legal tradition
post-independence.
The attributes of
both the United States and Australia, would lead to the expectation of a
liberal interpretation of international law. As discussed in the earlier parts
of his investigation, the attributes of the legal traditions of these states –
identical in all respects – lead to a disconnect between the recognition of the
binding authority of existing international law and the interpretation that
state decision-makers adopt.
An examination of the
pre-EU legal tradition of the United Kingdom would lead to the same
expectation. Prior to joining the European Union, the attributed of the U.K.’s
legal tradition were the same as those found in the U.S. and Australia. Again,
obviously, the historical development which led to these attributes differed
from that of the two other states, but the resulting attributes were similar
enough to produce an expectation of a liberal interpretation of international
law. However, the United Kingdom’s membership in the European Union has a
caused a shift in some of the attributes of the legal tradition. This is
particularly noticeable in the slight shift from an individual purpose of law
to a communal purpose of law, a movement from a strict dualist stance to a
mixed monist/dualist stance, and the increased recognition of statutory law as
the primary source of law. These shifts would be expected to create a closer
relationship between British domestic law and international law. This is
because, as discussed in chapters two and three, certain attributes facilitate
the internalization of international law, which creates a more binding sense of
obligation among decision-makers. Given this, expectations on Britain’s
interpretation would shift as well, and I would suggest the state could be
expected to adopt a traditional, rather than liberal, approach to the
international law of universal jurisdiction.
Finally, in the case
of India, what we might expect in terms of the pre-independence Indian legal
tradition differs from what would be expected from the post-independence
tradition. Prior to the arrival of the British, when India was still a country
dominated by religious legal traditions, it would be expected the state would
adopt a hierarchical interpretation of international law, just as Egypt does
due to the influence of the Islamic tradition. Post-independence, however,
after the common law influence of the British legal tradition has been
super-imposed over the historical religious origins, expectations change. The
shift from a religious tradition to a secular tradition has shifted some of the
attributes of the Indian tradition. While still largely focused on a communal
purpose of law, the secularization of the Indian tradition has shifted the
communal recognition from one based on religion to one based on nationalism. It
is possible this has a less profound effect on the societal understanding of law.
Moreover, with the
creation of British style legal institutions, there has been a shift in the
creation and amendment of law as well, from the religious based legal system,
to one in which a representative parliament is responsible for creating and
amending law.
There is also a much
greater role for the judiciary. In fact, the only attribute of the Indian legal
tradition which has not significantly changed over the course of the country’s
history is its strongly dualist approach to international law. There has never
existed an extremely close relationship between international law and Indian
domestic law. Again, this does not mean that India does not abide by or accept
international law, on the contrary, India like the U.S., the U.K., and
Australia is a country founded on the rule of law. What it does mean, however,
is that the relationship between domestic law and international law is less
likely to be absolute, and therefore, Indian decision-makers are less likely to
feel bound by existing international law, and more likely to therefore make
liberal interpretations of such law.
To summarize,
therefore, general expectations based on simple categorization of common law
countries would indicate all four states – the U.S., U.K., Australia, and India
– would adopt liberal interpretations of international law. Moreover,
traditional IR explanations focused on power and interests would hypothesize
that these states would similarly adopt an interpretation not requiring
adherence to the Rome Statute due to perceived dangers to state troops serving
abroad, and the relinquishment of state sovereign required to be a part of the
treaty. Our expectations, founded on the various attributes of legal tradition
rather than general categorizations, would be that the U.S., Australia, and
India would indeed adopt liberal interpretations of the international law of
universal jurisdiction – although for slightly different reasons – and the
U.K., largely due to its membership in the European Union, would adopt a
traditional interpretation. After examining the statements made by the four
states, it is clear that my expectations were met in three of the four cases.
The U.S., U.K., and India each adopted the method of interpretation expected.
Australia, on the other hand, rather than adopting a liberal interpretation as
they did in the case of the international norms of sic utere
adopted a traditional interpretation and signed on to the Rome Statute. While
Australia therefore did not meet expectations based on its attributes, an
explanation of Australia’s position in this instance can be found in a closer
examination of the historical development of its legal tradition. The position
adopted and justifications provided for each state in turn now.
First, the United
States was expected to adopt a liberal interpretation, and did in fact adopt
such as interpretation. As discussed in earlier chapters, the United States
recognized the legal principle at issue – indeed as in earlier cases was
instrumental in creating the legal principle at issue – but disagreed with the
existing interpretation of this principle as outlined in the Rome Statute of
the ICC. The United States provided a number of justifications for its position
on the Rome Statute. First, there is concern that adherence to the Statute of
the ICC would infringe upon the sovereignty of the United States in that it
would violate of the protections of due process provided by the United States
Constitution99. This would be contrary to the very foundation upon which the
U.S. legal tradition is built: the United States Constitution.100 The U.S. has
long been a supporter of the concept of universal jurisdiction. However, the
protections provided in the Statute of the ICC are not as stringent as those provided
in the U.S. Constitution. The U.S. cannot accept an international legal
principle which would be contrary to the Constitution.
Second, the United
States argued that, as the “world’s greatest military and economic power, more
than any other country the United States is expected to intervene to halt
humanitarian catastrophe around the world.”101 This unique position of the
U.S., government officials argued, makes U.S. personnel around the globe
“uniquely vulnerable” to malicious prosecutions by the ICC Prosecutor.102
Third, the U.S. was not satisfied with the language concerning the specific
reach of universal jurisdiction as outlined in the Rome Statute. The statute
allows for the ICC to have jurisdiction over any person, whether or not that
individual’s state is a member of the Court. The position of the U.S. is that
this is too broad a definition of universal jurisdiction, one that infringes
illegally according to international law on the sovereignty of those states
which choose not to become party to the ICC103.
India was also
expected to adopt a liberal interpretation and India did indeed adopt a liberal
interpretation, recognizing the existence of the international legal principle
of universal jurisdiction, but disagreeing with the interpretation of this
principle as laid out by the Rome Statute to the International Court of
Justice. Like the U.S., India had a number of specific justifications for its
disagreement with the Rome Statute. First, India seemed to express the
sentiment that it felt its concerns were not taken seriously enough during the
drafting of the Rome Statute.104 India believed that the expression of
universal jurisdiction in the Rome Statute was too broad in delineating the
situations which may be brought before the Court. India thus shared the
concerns of the other states that prosecutions may be brought before the Court
for political purposes.105 India was further concerned about the ability of the
Security Council to refer cases to the ICC in potential contravention of
international law.106 Further, India shared the reservations of the U.S. that
the Rome Statute’s power to prosecute nationals of non-party states was an
acceptable interpretation of the principle of universal jurisdiction.107
Finally, India, despite its own status as a nuclear state, was concerned about
the exclusion of the use of nuclear weapons and other weapons of mass
destruction as a crime within the jurisdiction of the ICC.108 India’s
interpretation of universal jurisdiction encompasses the belief that use of
such weapons is a crime abhorrent to the international community as a whole.
In many ways, the
situation of India and its interpretation of the international legal principle
of universal jurisdiction is similar to the case of Turkey and its
interpretation of the international legal principle of anticipatory
intervention in self-defense. In both cases you have fairly new democracies
with legal institutions largely based on those of other states trying to
increase their presence in the international system while at the same time
maintaining their sense of national identity and sovereignty after many years
under the thumb of others. And just as was the case with Turkey in part four,
India has been reluctant to relinquish sovereignty over its laws to the
international realm. And while India might be expected to sign on be to
demonstrate its recognition of human rights and its desire to move into the top
echelon of states in the international power structure (reputational issues,
etc.), India has not adopted the traditional interpretation of universal
jurisdiction.
India, of the four
countries, also has the least to lose by signing on, given its minimal troop
presence in UN operations, etc. What India does have, however, is a common law
tradition which has developed out of a historical legal tradition comprising customary,
Hindu, and Islamic law. These traditional legal influences are still present in
the India tradition, even with the development of common law-style institutions
and constitution. The historical traditions have on Indian policymakers
apparently influences their understanding of the purpose of law, and makes the
notion of subjecting Indian citizens to law which is not steeped in these
traditions unthinkable.
This theory is also
buoyed by the historical caste system in India which, while no longer legally
valid, still permeates society. Under this system, those of the upper castes
cannot be brought to trial by those of the lower castes. This applies internationally
as well.
The United Kingdom
also met expectations, adopting a traditional rather than a liberal
interpretation of the international legal principle of universal jurisdiction.
The United Kingdom ratified the Rome Statute of the International Criminal
Court on October 4, 2001.109 While this may seem somewhat surprising given the
United Kingdom’s place as the origin of the common law tradition and the fact
that the U.K. regularly has troops participating in NATO and other coalition
operations110, the membership of the U.K. in the European Union has done much
to alter the tradition attributes of the state’s legal tradition.
Moreover, the U.K.,
for most of its long history, has not had a Bill of Rights, so concerns like
those of the U.S. do not apply. Also, the U.K. has already agreed to relinquish
its sovereignty over certain human rights issues and international crimes to regional
bodies – the ECJ and the ECHR – so its legal tradition is already accustomed to
such action. The member states of the European Union, in fact, are “accustomed
to external supervision and even adjudication of their human rights practices.
… The process of European integration has forced these states to accept to a
considerable degree the pooling of their sovereignty.”111 This results in a
very different perception of the impact membership in the ICC and adherence to
the Rome Statute’s conception of universal jurisdiction would have on the
state’s sovereignty. Due to its adherence to the Rome Statute, the U.K. is not
less sensitive to the sacrifice of sovereignty than some of its common law
counterparts.
Australia is the sole
case out of the twelve examined in this project which did not meet
expectations. As in chapter five in the case of sic utere,
based on the attributes of the Australian tradition, we would have expected
Australia to adopt a liberal interpretation of the principle of universal
jurisdiction in this case. As with the U.S., we would have expected this to
manifest itself in Australia’s not signing on to the Rome State of the
International Criminal Court However, Australia did accept the Rome Statute’s
interpretation of the principle of universal jurisdiction and ratified the Rome
Statute on July 1, 2002.112. This is perhaps the most surprising case because
in so many ways the Australia legal tradition and its historical development
are similar to that of the U.S.
There is, however,
one key difference: Australia does not have a Bill of Rights. In the case of
human rights protections outlined by the principle of universal jurisdiction in
the Rome Statute to the ICC, given Australia’s somewhat rocky history with the
protection of rights, the concerns over misuse of the international legal
process by politically-motivated actors was likely minimized when balanced
against the desire to demonstrate the country’s adherence to human rights
protections. Moreover, the lack of a concrete bill of rights, such as is found
in the United States, means that there were no conflicts similar to those found
in the U.S. discourse of constitutional protections of due process.113 In fact,
in recent years, it has been suggested that precisely because Australia lacks a
comprehensive charter of rights, the country’s litigants and lawyers are
“turning to international law in the quest for a peg on which to hang arguments
designed to persuade Australian courts that part of international jurisprudence
has been, or should be, incorporated by judicial decision.”114 This particular
attitude towards human rights law originating from the attributes of the
Australian legal tradition, and differing from those of the other three states,
helps to explain why Australia adopted the method of interpretation they did in
the case of the Rome Statute of International Criminal Court, rather than a
more liberal interpretation as expected.
(B) How this is better than existing theories (both
those which focus on more general descriptions (common law/civil law etc.) and
the realist and NLI theories.
The subject of this
above research – that legal tradition explains the interpretations adopted by
states towards international law – correctly predicts the interpretations
adopted in three of the four states examined above, and provides an explanation
for the missed prediction in the case of the fourth state. This then provides a
much more complete picture of the influence of legal tradition on state
interpretation of the international legal principle of universal jurisdiction
as codified in the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court than other
international relations theories. First, those few works which do focus on
legal tradition, but only as the broadest of categories, such as common law,
would only have correctly predicted the outcomes for two of the four countries
in this chapter. More importantly, by focusing only on the common
characteristics among the common law states, these theories would have been
unable to provide a satisfactory explanation as to why two of the four states
defied expectations.
Performing even
worse, would have likely been more traditional international relations
explanations, which don’t consider legal tradition at all. Theories centered on
power and interests would have suggested, as outlined above, that the concept
of universal jurisdiction outlined in the Rome Statute of the ICC would have
only succeeded in becoming an accepted definition if supported by the most
powerful states. Given many of the most powerful states in the world – the
U.S., Russia, China, India, Australia – did not sign on, these theories would
predict none of the four states in this study would have joined the ICC. They
would have been wrong on all four counts.
Moreover,
interest-based theories would have suggested that signing on to an
international treaty such as the Rome Statute, which requires states to
relinquish a small amount of sovereignty is not in the state’s interests,
particular when perceived assistance with some collective action problem is
minimal due to the nature of the institution.
Moreover, as
described in the context of both part 3 and 4, however, this conception of interests only focuses
on the short-term material interests of a state. An examination of the
long-term interest of the state would lead to the conclusion that becoming a
party to the Rome Statute is actually more beneficial for the state because the
state then has the opportunity to participate in the workings of the ICC,
including drafting the Court’s procedures, selecting the prosecutor and the
justices, and participating in discussion over which cases should be heard115.
Particularly once it became clear that the Rome Statute was going to receive
the 60 ratifications required to enter into effect, it becomes in the state’s
interests to sign on to the Court. States do not tend to think in the
long-term, however, and in considering short term interests this theory would
not have successful predicted the outcomes either.
Certainly
consideration of interests mattered in each of the interpretations states made,
but as suggested by the theory of this project, the extent to which the
interests can be considered varies depending on the attributes of the legal
tradition. In the case of the U.K., for example, while protection of the
state’s numerous soldiers engaged in military actions abroad and protection of
U.K. citizens from politically-motivated prosecutions was likely as relevant to
the decision-makers in the United Kingdom as it was in any of the other three
states examined, the influence on its legal tradition and perceptions of the
appropriate course of action for the good of the community wielded by the
European Union mitigated the extent to which the U.K. policy-makers were able
to consider these interests.
Moreover, in this
specific case, since each of the four states examined is involved in sending
its military personnel to other countries – both on UN peace-keeping missions
and in relation to other armed conflicts – each of these states has the
potential for concern that its own military will be subject to prosecution by
the ICC for acts committed in the course of these actions, as well as a concern
over the potential for politically-motivated prosecutions. This is a very real
concern, for all four states116, as each has been (or is) involved in
situations in which their presence is unpopular. For example, India has troops
in Sierra Leone acting as peacekeepers under the auspices of the United
Nations.
The Commander in
Sierra Leone is an Indian national named Major General Vijay Kumar Jetley, who has come under fire for actions perceived by
other states as invalid, despite the highest praise from former UN Secretary
General Kofi Annan117. This is exactly the type of situation states fear could
lead to malicious prosecution. Yet, as has been demonstrated, two of the states
signed on to the Rome Statute of International Criminal Court anyway. Therefore
concern over the interests of one’s own military cannot be the primary reason
for a state’s interpretation of its obligations under the ICC statute.
Furthermore,
arguments that the positions of the four states might be politically motivated,
particularly in the case of the United States, are unfounded. Two of the four
states have had shifts in party power since the opening for signature of the
Statute of the International Criminal Court. However, each has maintained a
constant position on its interpretation of its obligations under the Court. For
example, the United States participated in negotiations for the Rome Statute
largely under the auspices of the Clinton Administration. Indeed the U.S. and
its allies worked very hard to come to a compromise that would allow the United
States to participate in the new world court118. While Clinton did sign the
Rome Statute on behalf of the U.S., however, he warned that neither he, nor his
predecessor would be able to ratify the Statute in its existing form.
India too has
experienced shifts in political power through the period, with three different
major parties or party coalitions heading the government from the 1998 to 2004
period.
None of these have
changed the position of India that it cannot sign on to the interpretation of
universal jurisdiction as outlined in the Rome Statute. Australia, on the other
hand, has had the same party in power since John Howard’s Liberal Party was elected
in 1996. And while its ratification took some time (the country signed the Rome
Statute on December 9, 1998 and did not ratify it until July 1, 2002, after it
had already entered into effect by virtue of receiving 60 ratifications)119,the
ultimate support for the becoming a member of the ICC cut across party lines,
in the same way agreement not to support the charter cut across party lines in
the U.S. Even the Chief of the Australian Defense Force stated that he believed
the “creation of the ICC would be no threat to Australian forces, rather the
Court’s existence would make Australian soldiers’ jobs easier and safer in
peace-keeping situations.”121 This is even in light of many who suggested that
Australia’s acceptance of the Rome Statute would “constitute a serious
diminution of Australian sovereignty – that Australian nationals, including defence force personnel on international peace operations,
could be tried by the court against the will of the Australian Government.”121
Based on the research
presented above, expectations were met in three of the four situations examined
in this case. In the fourth case, a closer examination of the state’s legal
tradition provides a logical explanation for its divergence. As demonstrated
this explanatory power is more successful than any of the alternative theories,
and provides significant additional support for the importance of consideration
of the attributes and historical development of a state’s legal tradition.
State Behaviour in the International System
P.1
State Behaviour in the International System
P.2
State Behaviour in the International System
P.3
State Behaviour in the International System
P.4
State Behaviour in the International System
P.6
1 Each of the four
states has a long history of participating in UN peacekeeping operations. See
U.S. Department of State Background Notes for each state, available at
http://www.state.gov. For example, India is cited as “having a long tradition
of participating in UN peacekeeping operations and most recently contributed
personnel to UN operations in Somalia, Cambodia, Mozambique, Kuwait, Bosnia, El
Salvador,and Lebanon.”
2 David B. Rivkin,
Jr. and Lee A. Casey, “Crimes Outside the World’s Jurisdiction,” New York
Times, 2003, http://www.westlaw.com (2003 WLNR 5656698).
3 Mark W. Janis,
Introduction to International Law (New York: Aspen Publishers, 2003), 329.
4 Ibid.; Rivkin and
Casey, “Crimes Outside the World’s Jurisdiction.”
5 Michael P. Scharf, “Results
of the Rome Conference for an International Criminal Court,” ASIL
Insights, August 1998, http://www.asil.org/insights (accessed April 2007).
6 Janis, Introduction
to International Law, 329. In Filartiga v.
Peña-Irala, the 2nd Circuit stated, “the torturer has become – like the pirate
and slave trader before him – hostis humani generis, an enemy of all mankind”. The 6th Circuit,
in Demjanjuk v. Petrovsky, seconded this idea five years later when deciding
whether Israel had universal jurisdiction over a Nazi war criminal even though
his crimes were committed prior to the creation of Israel as a state:
“[N]either the nationality of the accused or the victim(s), nor the location of
the crime is significant. The underlying assumption is that the crimes are
offenses against the law of nations or against humanity and that the
prosecuting nation is acting for all nations.”.
7 Stefaan Smis and
Kim Van der Borght, “Belgian law concerning The Punishment of Grave Breaches of
International Humanitarian Law: A Contested Law with Uncontested Objectives,”
ASIL Insights, July 2003, http://www.asil.org/insights (accessed April 2007).
8 Leila Nadya Sadat,
“The International Criminal Court Treaty Enters into Force,” ASIL Insights,
April 2002, http://www.asil.org/insights (accessed April 2007).
9 Ibid., quoting Rome
Statute of the International Criminal Court, United Nations Diplomatic
Conference of Plenipotentiaries on the Establishment of an International
Criminal Court, July 17, 1998,Annex II, U.N. Doc A/CONF. 183/9 (1998), Preamble
& art. 5(1).
10 David Wippman, “The International Criminal Court,” in The
Politics of International Law, ed. Christian Reus-Smit (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004), 152.
11 Ibid., 152-53.
12 Ibid., 153.
13 This refers also
to a forthcoming book by Simmons.
14 Rene David and
John E.C. Brierley, Major Legal Systems in the World Today, 3rd ed. (London:
Stevens & Sons, 1985), 306, 311.
15 Ibid., 312-313.
16 Ibid., 358.
“English jurists think of their law as essentially a case law. …”
17 Ibid., 307-335.
18 This notion
largely gained traction in England through the work of Jeremy Bentham
(1748-1832). David and Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 330; Glendon,
Gordon, and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 316. Bentham and his
followers “had little respect for tradition and the sanctity of precedent
…(and) viewed the common law as inordinately slow in responding to social
needs. They urged codification to provide certainty and comprehension to the
law, and to avoid a social revolution.”
19 This has changed
somewhat, however, with the U.K.’s membership in the European Union and passage
of the U.K. Human Rights Act in 1998. These events have increased the power of
the British courts to review the acts of parliament for conformance with provisions
of these documents. See Glendon, Gordon and Osakwe, Comparative Legal
Traditions, 357; “United Kingdom,” in Legal Systems of the World: A Political,
Social and Cultural Encyclopedia, ed. Herbert M. Kritzer (Santa Barbara, CA:
ABCCLIO, 2002), 1699. K., 1699.
20 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 439. “Within the body of federal
legislation, a special place is quite naturally occupied by the fundamental
national law, the Constitution. … For Americans it represents a good deal more
than the French Constitution does for Frenchmen. It is not only a political
charters but the nation’s founding document, inspired by the ideas of the
Natural Law School and one which put into operation the concept of social
contract.”
21 Ibid., 383.
22 The Magna Carta,
passed in 1215, was a charter enacted between King John and the English barons.
The barons were upset over their increasing loss of jurisdiction (and hence
revenue) over legal matters. While primarily a document designed to preserve the
power and revenue of the barons over certain local judicial issues, the charter
also contained some provisions protecting ordinary citizens such as habeas
corpus and due process provisions such as the right to a jury trial. See
Glendon, Gordon and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 310; Constitutions of
the World, 2nd ed., ed. Robert L. Maddox (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2001),
368-369.
23 The Bill of Rights
of 1689 provided that the monarch could not dispense with the laws, not suspend
the laws without the consent of parliament. This bill also established the
principle of the freedom of speech in Parliament. See “United Kingdom,” Legal
Systems of the World, 1695.
24 The European
Communities Act joined the United Kingdom to the European Union (the
Community). This added EU law as a new source of law for England, one with
which no domestic provision of law could conflict. This is one of the acts that
has given the British courts a bit more authority of judicial review in that
they may review acts of parliament for conformance with EU law. See Glendon,
Gordon and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 656.
25 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 406. “The American attitude towards the
law is not that of the English.”
26 Constitutions of
the World, 370. “The first generally recognized individual rights in England
were those under common law: the right inherent in access to the monarch’s
courts for remedies even against feudal lords.”
27 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 331.
28 Glendon, Gordon
and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 593. “Paramount is a sensitivity for
preserving an individual right to contract freely and to alienate property.”
29 Ibid., 325;
Constitutions of the World, 370.
30 Glendon, Gordon
and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 325.
31 Ibid., 350-351.
32 Ibid., 351. “Some
unpopular decisions, widely condemned as unduly partial towards the King’s interests,
discredited the idea that Parliament’s authority was limited by judicially
enforceable laws… .”
33 Ibid., 352.
34 Ibid., 349.
35 Constitutions of
the World, 370. “The one indisputable fact is the supremacy of the British
parliament, which in theory precludes judicial review. As Sir William
Blackstone quoted in his famous legal commentaries: ‘The power and jurisdiction
of parliament … is so transcendent and absolute, that it
cannot be confined either for causes or persons, within any bounds.’”
36 “United Kingdom,”
Legal Systems of the World, 1699. “The United Kingdom adopts a dualist approach
to international law, which is therefore not a direct source of law within the
U.K.”
37 Rosalyn Higgins,
Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1994), 205; “The Growing Rapprochement Between International Law and
National Law”, in Visions of Legal Order in the 21st Century: Essays to Honour His Excellency Judge C.J. Weermantry,
ed. G. Sturgess and A. Anghie,
http://www.hcourt.gov.au/speeches/kirbyj/kirbyj_weeram.htm (accessed January 8,
2005).
38 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 383.
39 Ibid., at 439.
40 Glendon, Gordon
and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 657.
41 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 366.
42 “United Kingdom,”
Legal Systems of the World, 1699. “The absence of a written constitution,
coupled with the doctrine of parliamentary supremacy, means that as a general
rule, Parliament’s primary legislation may make or unmake any law.”
43 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 386. “For English jurists, there is no
true legal rule except that which is seen through the facts of a case and,
therefore, reduced to that principle which is required to resolve that dispute.
This traditionalism … prevents English statutes from achieving fully a
status in the hierarchy of sources equivalent to continental European
legislation and codes.”
44 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 366; Glendon, Gordon and Osakwe,
Comparative Legal Traditions, 593. “Although there is no dispute that
legislation increasingly is assuming a major role as a source of law, the
fabric of the common law is its precedent, and the vast number of volumes of
such cases is the foremost distinguishing feature of the common law tradition.”
45 Kenneth R.
Simmonds, “United Kingdom,” International Encyclopedia of Comparative Law:
National Reports, Vol. I, ed. Viktor Knapp (Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1973), U-69.
46 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 366. “[T]he influence of legal writing
has been less in England than on the continent. …”
47 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 353.
48 Simmonds, “United
Kingdom,” U-71. However, certain works, written for the most part by judges,
have become part of a “canon” of British legal literature which are referred to
throughout the common law world. Authors include Glanville, Bracton,
Littleton, and above all, Coke. David and Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd
ed., 394.
49 “India,” Legal
Systems of the World: A Political, Social and Cultural Encyclopedia, Vol. II,
ed. Herbert M. Kritzer (Santa Barbara, CA: ABC-CLIO, Inc., 2002), 693; CIA
World Factbook: India, http://www.cia.gov (accessed April 2007).
50 U.S. Department of
State Background Notes: India, December 2006, http://www.state.gov.
51 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 508-509 (“Indian law, shaped by English
lawyers and judges, is necessarily a part of the Common law family.”).
52 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 508. “The rules of India could not be
any but those of English law. They have been shaped by the context of, and make
of the concepts derived from, the Common law system.”; “The Legal System of the
Republic of India,” Modern Legal Systems Cyclopedia,
Vol. 9, revised ed., ed. Linda L. Schlueter (Buffalo, NY: William S. Hein &
Co, 2001), 9.80.25. “The modern judicial system in India had its beginnings
under British auspices in the late eighteenth century and was extended and
consolidated during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Its legal concepts
and
procedures resemble those of Anglo-Saxon countries.”
53 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 486.
54 Ibid, 486.
55 Ibid, 486.
56 Ibid, 486.
57 The four groups
are the Brahmin, the Kshatriyas or Vaishayas, the
Sudras, and the untouchables. The Brahmin are the scholars and priests of
society. The rules for the group are classified in the dharmasastras
and dharmasutra. The Kshatriyas and Vaishayas are the warriors and merchants respectively, and
are considered those primarily responsible for running the government. The
rules for this class are governed by artha, or
expediency, and are held in the arthasastras or arthasutras. The Sudras are the artisans and tradesmen of
society. The rules for this class are governed by kama,
or pleasure, and are
held in the kamasastras or kamasutras.
For each of these three classes, it is believed all persons have elements of
the dharma, artha, and kama,
however, depending on their social class, their lives must be dominated by the
rules for that class. This is the only way to preserve the harmonic balance of
the
universe. The fourth class, the poor, the untouchables, does not have a body of
rules outlined by Hinduism.
For a broader discussion of the Hindu legal tradition, see "India,"
Legal Systems of the World, at 693; David and Brierley, Major Legal Systems,
3rd ed., 484-515;
58 “India,” Legal
Systems of the World, 693.
59 “The Legal System
of the Republic of India,” Modern Legal Systems Cyclopedia, 9.80.7.
60 Ibid., 9.80.9.
61 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 490.
62 Ibid., 490;
“India,” Legal Systems of the World, 694.
63 David and Brierley,
Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 490; P.K. Irani, “India,” in International
Encyclopedia of Comparative Law: National Reports, Vol. I., ed. Viktor Knapp,
(Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1973), I-12.
64 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 491.
65 Glendon, Gordon,
and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 320. India was a colony “seeded” by
Britain. There were three different methods the British used, seeded, settled
and conquered. Seeded nations, like India, were those in which elements of British
law were introduced into a society which already had a relatively advanced
legal system. Settled nations were those in which there was a native
population, but one without a sufficient infrastructure to withstand the
imposition of the British system. The United States is an example of a settled
colony. Conquered nations were those in which an element of force was used to
wrest power from another authority. An example of this is South Africa, in
which the British took over from the Dutch who had already “settled” the
territory.
66 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 491.
67 Ibid., at 491.
68 Ibid., 493. This
“did help to reduce the great diversity of local customs which, even to Hindus,
was considered a drawback. Moreover, the contributed to an evolution which many
consider beneficial in so far as it modernized Hindu law while respecting its
spirit.”
69 Constitutions of
the World, 156. “British hegemony was unifying for India, because it imposed a
single administrative and court system, improved transportation and
communication, and brought education to a new professional class.”
70 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 491; “India,” Legal Systems of the
World, 694.
71 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 513. “Having been subject to foreign
ruling powers for centuries, Indians today are deeply united by, and are justly
proud of, the independence they gained through the non-violent means required
by their religious beliefs.”
72 Constitutions of
the World, 156-157.
73 Glendon, Gordon,
and Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, 39.
74 “India,” Legal
Systems of the World, 696.
75 Constitution of
India (1950), as amended, Preamble,
http://indiacode.nic.in/coiweb/welcome.html.
76 Ibid., Article 15.
77 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 513
78 “The Legal System
of the Republic of India,” Modern Legal Systems Cyclopedia, 9.80.24;
Constitutions of the World, 157. “Part 4 contains … principles … for securing a
social order and promoting the welfare of the people.”
79 “The Legal System
of the Republic of India,” Modern Legal Systems Cyclopedia, 9.80.24.
80 Ibid., 9.80.16.
81 “India,” Legal
Systems of the World, 696.
82 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 513.
83 “India,” Legal
Systems of the World, 696
84 Irani, “India,”
I-11. “Judicial decisions in India have the force of precedent. Judgments of
the Supreme Court are binding on all courts in India and judgments of the High
Court are binding on all subordinate courts in the State.”
85 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 488.
86 Ibid., 489.
87 Ibid., 498.
88 Ibid.
89 Ibid. Hindu law …
retains its place as one of the fundamental notions of the social order in the
modern world.”
90 “The Legal System
of the Republic of India,” Modern Legal Systems Cyclopedia, 9.80.29; “India,”
Legal Systems of the World, 697.
91 David and
Brierley, Major Legal Systems, 3rd ed., 511-512; “The Legal System of the
Republic of India,” Modern Legal Systems Cyclopedia, 9.80.21
92 Constitutions of
the World, 156. “The Indian constitution, a long and detailed document,
attempts to maintain democracy while transforming a rigid, hierarchical social
order into an egalitarian state.”
97 U.S. Department of
State Background Note: United Kingdom, February 2007, http://www.state.gov.
“The U.K. was the United States’ main coalition partner in Operation Iraqi
Freedom and continues to have more than 8,000 troops deployed in Iraq to help
stabilize and rebuild the country.”; “Australia was one of the earliest
participants in Operation Enduring Freedom. Australian Defense Forces
participated in coalition military action against Iraq in Operation Iraqi
Freedom. Australian military and civilian specialists are participating in the
training of Iraqi security forces and the reconstruction of Iraq. Australian
Special Forces redeployed to Afghanistan to help provide security for the
country's September 18, 2005 elections.”
98 CIA World
Factbook: India, http://www.cia.gov, (accessed April 2007).
99 Barbara Crossette,
“U.S. Pushes to Weaken World Court on Atrocities,” New York Times, June 12,
2000, http://www.westlaw.com (2000 WLNR 3234890). “Critics of the court object
to what they say is the legal authority it would have without an acceptable constitutional
base. John Bolton, a former assistant secretary of state for international
organizations in the Bush administration, calls the establishment of the court
“a stealth approach to eroding our constitutionalism”… .””
100 U.S. Senator Rod
Grams, “Is a UN International Criminal Court in the U.S. National Interest?,”
Committee on Foreign Relations, United States Senate, 105th Congress, 2nd
Session, July 23, 1998, 8. “When Congressional and other ICC critics complain
that ‘this Court strikes at the heart of sovereignty’, they are not spouting
empty rhetoric; instead, at some level, they are appealing to deeply held
conceptions of national identity and the proper relationship between law and self government.”, as quoted in Wippman,
“The International Criminal Court,” 163.
101 Scharf, “Results
of the Rome Conference.”
102 Ibid.
103 Ibid. quoting
David Scheffer, U.S. Ambassador-at-Large for War Crimes Issues speaking to the
Senate Foreign Relations Committee, “Out position is
clear: Official actions of a non-party state should not be subject to the
court’s jurisdiction if that country does not join the treaty, except by means
of Security Council action under the U.N. Charter.”
104 Dilip Lahiri,
Explanation of vote on the adoption of the Statute of the International
Criminal Court, 1998, http://www.indianembassy.org (accessed April 2007).
Statement by Mr. Lahiri, Additional Secretary to the United Nations: “As the
world’s largest democracy, which is fortunate to have in addition one of the
most independent and far-sighted judiciaries in the world, whose contribution
to the jurisprudence on the rights of individuals is almost unmatched, we would
have wanted to be one of the first signatories of the ICC; equally, it should
have been in the interests of the ICC to have a country like India on board.”
105 Ibid.
106 Ibid.
107 Ibid. Statement
by Mr. Lahiri, Additional Secretary to the United Nations: “But while we tried,
unsuccessfully, to ensure that the Court would be free from political
influence, and its Statute in full conformity with the Law of Treaties, on the
penultimate day of the Conference, the purists resurrected and forces into the
Statute the concept of universal or inherent jurisdiction, which too makes a
mockery of the distinction between States Parties and those who choose not to
be bound by a treaty.” It is truly unfortunate that a Statute drafted for an
institution to defend the law should start out straying so sharply from
established international law.”
108 Ibid.
109 International
Criminal Court website, http://www.icc-cpi.int (accessed April 2007).
110 U.S. Department
of State Background Note: United Kingdom, http://www.state.gov.
111 Wippman, “The Original Criminal Court,” 161.
112 Hon. Alexander
Downer, Minister for Foreign Affairs, Australia, “Australia Ratifies
International Criminal Court: News Release”, 2002,
http://www.foreignminister.gov.au/releases.
113 Constitutions of
the World, 19-20. An attempt was made to enact a Bill of Rights in Australia in
1988. It was defeated in a national referendum.
114 The Hon. Justice
Michael Kirby, “Domestic Implementation of International Human Rights in
Australia,” Australian National University Faculty of Law, Conference on
Implementing International Human Rights, Saturday December 6, 1997,
http://www.hcourt.gov.au (accessed February 2005).
115 Sir Ninian
Stephen, “Australia must ratify the international court”. The Age, 2002,
http://www.theage.com.au (accessed April 2007). Sir Ninian Stephen, former
governor-general of Australia, High Court judge, and Justice of the
International Criminal Tribunals for Rwanda and the former Yugoslavia,
summarizes this position for Australia: “Perhaps even more significantly, if we
choose not to ratify the statute … we will forfeit the opportunity to be
involved in the critically important process of selecting a prosecutor for the
court and we will be unable to have Australians employed by the court.”;
Scharf, “Results of the Rome Conference.” Professor Michael Scharf speaking to
the Senate Foreign Relations Committee: "Within five years the world will
have a permanent international criminal court even without U.S. support. As a
non-party, the U.S. will not be bound to cooperate with the Court. But this
does not guarantee complete immunity from the Court. It is important to
understand that U.S. citizens, soldiers, and officials could still be indicted
by the Court and even arrested and surrendered to the Court while they are
present in a foreign country which happens to be a party to the Court's
Statute. Moreover, by failing to sign the Statute, the U.S. will be prevented
from participating in the preparatory committee which will draft the Court's
Rules of Procedure and further define the elements of the crimes within the
Court's jurisdiction. Also, by failing to sign the Statute, the U.S. will be
prevented from nominating a candidate for the Court's bench, participating in
the selection of the Court's Prosecutor and judges, or voting on its
funding."
116 Alessandra
Stanley, “U.S. Specifies Terms for War Crimes Court,” New York Times, July
10,1998, http://www.westlaw.com (1998 WLNR 2971970). “Washington’s primary
objection is thatAmerican soldiers might be
vulnerable to politically motivated charges. … We constantly have troops
serving abroad on humanitarian missions, rescue operations or missions to
destroy weapons of mass destruction. Someone out there isn’t going to like it,
but we are the ones who do it.”
117 Crossette, “U.N.
Chief Faults Reluctance of U.S. to Help in Africa.”
118 Scharf, “Results
of the Rome Conference.”
119 Ratification of
the Rome Statute, United Nations Treaty Database, http://www.un.org/law/icc
120 Andrew MacLeod and
Greg Barns, “The International Criminal Court will strengthen Australia’s
global standing,” On-Line Opinion” Australia’s E-journal of Social and
Political Debate, 2002, http://www.onlineopinion.com.au (accessed, April 2007).
121 Ninian,
“Australian ratify the international court.”
For updates
click homepage here